The role of context in case-based legal reasoning:

teleological, temporal, and procedural

 

CAROLE D. HAFNER and DONALD H. BERMAN

Northeastern University, Boston MA 02115, USA

E-mail: hafner@ccs.neu.edu

 

 

 

Abstract. Computational models of relevance in case-based legal reasoning have traditionally been

based on algorithms for comparing the facts and substantive legal issues of a prior case to those

of a new case. In this paper we argue that robust models of case-based legal reasoning must also

consider the broader social and jurisprudential context in which legal precedents are decided. We

analyze three aspects of legal context: the teleological relations that connect legal precedents to the

social values and policies they serve, the temporal relations between prior and subsequent cases in a

legal domain, and the procedural posture of legal cases, which defines the scope of their precedential

relevance. Using real examples drawn from appellate courts of New York and Massachusetts, we

show with the courts own arguments that the doctrine of stare decisis (i.e., similar facts should lead

to similar results) is subject to contextual constraints and influences. For each of the three aspects of

legal context, we outline an expanded computational framework for case-based legal reasoning that

encompasses the reasoning of the examples, and provides a foundation for generating a more robust

set of legal arguments.

1. Introduction

Prediction is a fundamental component of legal reasoning, as the legal realists

demonstrated (Holmes 1897) and as practicing attorneys well understand. When

an attorney drafts a will for a client who has children but who wishes to leave

all of his property to his wife, the attorney predicts that a court will enforce the

clients written intention. When advising a client on a tax deduction, the attorney

predicts how a tax court will interpret the relevant statutes and regulations. In

advising a client whether to settle a case or accept a plea bargain, the attorney

predicts whether a trial will result in a decision more favorable than the deal that

lies on the bargaining table. From the standpoint of case-based legal reasoning,

when deciding which cases to cite in a legal argument before a judge, the attorney

makes a prediction whether the court is likely to follow a prior case or not.

Research in case-based legal reasoning has led to significant advances in modelling

the way lawyers use previously decided cases. Some models generate legal

arguments that to some degree simulate human adversarial discourse (Ashley 1990;

Skalak and Rissland 1992; Aleven and Ashley 1994). Others represent case-based

techniques for interpreting open-textured statutory predicates (Gardner 1987; Mc-

20 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Carty and Sridharan 1981; Sanders 1994; Rissland and Skalak 1991; Branting

1991). Taken as a whole, this body of research models the process of adversarial,

precedent-based legal reasoning and argumentation with an elegance and precision

not found in any comparable legal text.

However, the ability of most of these models to simulate the reasoning of practicing

attorneys is limited by their exclusive focus on the factual similarity between a

prior case and a new case. Real-world legal precedents are embedded in a complex

jurisprudential context that includes the level and jurisdiction of the prior court

(Berman 1989), the procedural posture of the prior case (i.e., what formal claim

or motion was before the court), and the influence of dissenting opinions. Legal

precedents are also embedded in a political context, where competing policies

and values are balanced by the courts, and where legal doctrines evolve to accommodate

new social and economic realities. Contextual factors such as these

are considered by skillful attorneys when they make predictions about whether a

precedent is likely to be followed, and whether a legal argument is likely to prevail.

As a result, computational models that do not take account of context fall short of a

robust analysis of the case-based legal reasoning performed by a practicing lawyer.

This paper, in which we consider the influence of the larger jurisprudential

and social context on precedent-based legal reasoning and argumentation, includes

research presented at three successive meetings of the International Conference

on Artificial Intelligence and Law (Berman and Hafner 1991, 1993, 1995).1 We

demonstrate that comparing the facts and issues of a new case with those of prior

cases to determine which cases are the most on point, while essential, is not a

sufficient basis for robust models of legal case-based reasoning. We analyze three

aspects of legal context: the teleological structure of a legal domain (Section 3),

the temporal relationships between prior and subsequent cases in a legal domain

(Section 4), and the procedural posture of the prior case (Section 5). Using real

examples drawn from appellate courts of New York and Massachusetts, we show

with the courts own arguments that the doctrine of stare decisis (i.e., similar facts

should lead to similar results) is subject to contextual constraints and influences.

For each of the three types of context, we propose an expanded computational

framework for case-based legal reasoning that encompasses the reasoning of the

examples.

By incorporating context into case-based legal reasoning, we are able to explain

several important phenomena in case-based legal reasoning that have not been

captured by earlier studies:

the use of policy arguments to choose between competing on-point precedents.

the ability to recognize when a factually on-point precedent is procedurally

inapt.

the ability to recognize when the most on-point precedent is unlikely to be

followed because more recent decisions weaken its authority.

The representation framework developed in this paper also points the way toward a

model of legal reasoning capable of recognizing and exploiting analogies between

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 21

different legal domains, both factual (such as duck hunting and education) and

doctrinal (such as tort and contract law).

2. Models of case-based legal reasoning

The formalization of law and legal reasoning is not a new enterprise, but rather

one that has challenged philosophers of law throughout the 20th century. Wesley

Hohfeld (1913), a legal positivist, proposed that all legal states of affairs can be

described in terms of four fundamental relations: rights, duties, powers and liabilities

(with inverse relations: no-rights, privileges, disabilities and immunities).

In contrast, legal realists such as Jerome Frank (1948) argued that law cannot be

characterized as a formal system, because the unlimited variety of fact patterns in

human affairs make legal decision-making inherently unpredictable. The problem

of open-textured concepts (i.e., legal concepts that do not have clear definitions to

determine their applicability, but which depend on experience and common sense,

such as the concept of recklessness) is the focus of a famous debate between H. L.

A. Hart and Lon Fuller (Hart 1958; Fuller 1958), in which a legal rule stating No

vehicles are permitted in the park is used to demonstrate that even an apparently

clear concept such as vehicle can be legally indeterminate, as in the case where

a veterans group wants to drive a tank through the park as part of a Memorial

Day parade. Fuller explained the difficulty of creating fixed definitions for legal

concepts by observing that the terms in a legal rule cannot be interpreted without

taking into account the purposes the rule is intended to serve.

With the advent of computers and artificial intelligence (AI), both the range

of techniques available and the practical motivation for creating legal reasoning

models have grown. In particular, researchers have made significant advances in

modeling the way lawyers classify, analyze and argue with cases, using a variety

of computational approaches including frames, transition nets, semantic networks,

discrimination trees, and neural networks (Ashley 1990; Aleven and Ashley 1994;

Branting 1991, 1994; Gardner 1987; Hafner 1981, 1987; Rissland et al. 1996; Rose

1994; Rissland and Skalak 1991). The legal reasoning model employed in this

paper is based on a computational framework (originating in the HYPO project

described below) that adapts and extends general AI techniques for case-based

reasoning to the domain of legal precedents. In this section, we briefly review

the HYPO framework, focusing on the use of a case knowledge base to support

the adversarial process of legal argumentation. Other frameworks for legal argumentation

based on formal logic (Prakken and Sartor 1997; Gordon 1994) and

on explicit models of legal discourse (Hage et al. 1994; Loui and Norman 1995)

are not reviewed here, although our analysis of the influence of context on legal

decisions could equally well apply to those frameworks.

The field of case-based reasoning in artificial intelligence (AI) is concerned with

the use of remembered prior experiences in analyzing new situations and solving

problems (Leake 1996). The distinguishing characteristic of case-based reasoning

22 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

is that prior experiences are stored as distinct histories or cases, in contrast to

other AI reasoning frameworks where knowledge (however acquired) is integrated

into a unified structure of logical rules, frames, neural nets, or combinations of

these. Thus, case-based reasoning uses knowledge that is more contextualized than

that used by other reasoning models, and relies more on powerful and effective

memory mechanisms and less on powerful and effective inference algorithms

(Riesbeck and Schank 1989).

Research in case-based legal reasoning, as practiced in the field of AI and law,

has a more restricted meaning: formal judicial decisions (that is, legal cases) play

the role of remembered experiences, and the problem-solving goal is the construction

of precedent-based adversarial legal arguments.2 The thrust of this research

has been aimed at creating models of relevance based on the similarity between the

facts and legal issues of a prior case and those of a new case. In these models, a

set of domain-dependent, legally-relevant factors is defined, and each prior case is

considered more or less on point depending on the similarity between its factors

and those of the new case.3 Implicitly, such models embody the following prediction:

the more similar the factors of a prior case are to those of a new case, the

stronger the prior cases precedential value that is, the more likely it is that a

court will follow it in deciding the new case.

Computational models of case-based legal reasoning are concerned with the

following problems:

i. Representation of cases, including what information should be included (facts,

issues, holdings, results, and justification) and what formalism(s) should be

used.

ii. Organization of the case base (including indexing attributes and index structure)

and retrieval of cases that are potentially relevant to a new case.

iii. Similarity ranking of the retrieved cases to decide which are the most relevant

to the new case.

iv. Creating a legal argument for each side, using the most relevant cases retrieved.

One of the earliest AI systems to represent legal cases, the Legal Research System

(LRS) (Hafner 1981) was a retrieval system for cases in negotiable instruments law.

LRS used a framelike slot-filler structure to encode the main elements of cases:

Plaintiff, Defendant, Cause of Action, Facts, Hypotheticals, Legal-Criteria, Legal-

Effects, and Holdings. The fillers of the slots were symbolic descriptions of legal

concepts: those concepts that appeared in the last three slots comprised the legal

issues of the case. The justification (or ratio decidendi) of the decision given by

the court was encoded as part of the Holdings slot. The LRS system retrieved cases

with matching facts, issues, and ratios based on queries rather than a description

of a new case; it did not perform similarity ranking, nor did it construct legal

arguments.

The first complete case-based legal reasoning model, one that addressed all four

of the problems above, was embodied in HYPO (Rissland and Ashley 1987; Ashley

1990),4 a computer program for analyzing cases and constructing legal arguments

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 23

in the domain of trade secrets law. HYPO used a multi-level description of cases:

facts and factual predicates represented the underlying circumstances of a case,

and a library of dimensions (selected by the systems designers, based on a survey

of relevant legal authorities) were used to index and retrieve cases.

A dimension in the HYPO model is a domain-specific factor, representing a

fact pattern that influences the outcome of cases in the domain (Rissland et al.

1984). Dimensions form an intermediate level of abstraction, between the facts of

a case (defendant hired an employee who previously worked for plaintiff), and

the top-level legal issues (defendant misappropriated plaintiffs trade secrets)

whose resolution determines which side wins. Dimensions in HYPO can be binary,

multi-valued, or quantitative; for example, in the trade secrets domain a

binary factor is Generally-Known, indicating that the alleged secret information

is generally known within the industry, and a quantitative factor is Secrets-

Voluntarily-Disclosed, representing the number of people to whom the plaintiff

told the information.

HYPOs legal domain knowledge includes, for each dimension, which side of

a dispute would be favored by the factors having particular values (e.g., a true

value for binary dimensions, or a larger value for quantitative dimension), and how

the factors value is related to a cases underlying facts. For example, in the trade

secrets domain, a true value for Generally-Known favors the defendant; a false

value favors the plaintiff.

When a new case is presented to HYPO, the dimensions applicable to the new

case are computed. Then, HYPO constructs a claim lattice a similarity network

that has the new case as its root node, and prior cases that share a maximal set

of dimensions with the new case as its immediate successors. These immediate

successors are called the most-on-point cases. The claim lattice would be further

populated with other on-point cases (those sharing at least one factor-value with

the new case), ordered by the subset relation (i.e., if the set of shared dimensions

of one prior case properly includes the set of shared dimensions for another prior

case, then the first case is more on point and is ranked higher than the second

case.)

Figure 1 illustrates an imaginary HYPO-style knowledge base; Figure 2 illustrates

a claim lattice for a hypothetical new case Smith v. Jones. There are three

most-on-point precedents, each sharing two dimensions with the new case. Precedents

whose shared dimensions with the new case are a proper subset of another

precedent are its successors in the claim lattice. Since Smith v. Jones has both

factors favoring the plaintiff (F1 and F6) and factors favoring the defendant (F3

and F5), it represents a typical hard case in which legal arguments can be made

for either side.5

After building the claim lattice to determine the most-on-point precedents and

the best cases for each side, HYPO constructs a 3-ply argument for each side in

the new case. Letting Side1 represent the party on whose behalf HYPO is arguing,

first a Point for Side 1 is produced making a claim that Side1 should win, next a

24 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Figure 1. A HYPO-style case knowledge base for a legal domain.

Figure 2. Claim lattice for Smith v. Jones.

Response for Side2 is produced, countering the claim, and then a Rebuttal for Side

1 is produced to answer the response. To create the initial claim for Side1, HYPO

identifies the most on point case(s) whose result favored Side1, and justifies the

claim by noting the similarity between the new case and the most on point cases.

Responses and rebuttals use the legal argument techniques of distinguishing and

presenting counter-examples. (Ashley 1990, p. 71).

For example, in Smith v. Jones the most on point cases for the plaintiff are

Arthur v. Beale and Isaac v. Jackson. The most-on-point cases for the defendant

are Carson v. DeWitt and Grantham v. Hodge. The following 3-ply argument could

be generated from this claim lattice:

Point for Plaintiff as Side1:

Where F1 and F3 are present, plaintiff should win its claim. Cite: Arthur v.

Beale. Also, where F6 is present, plaintiff should win. Cite: Isaac v. Jackson.

Response for Defendant as Side2:

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 25

Arthur v. Beale is distinguishable because: in Arthur v. Beale F5 was not

present. Cite: Grantham v. Hodge, which held for Defendant when F5 was

present.

Carson v. DeWitt is a counter-example to Isaac, since it held for defendant even

though F6 was present.

Therefore, defendant should win.

Rebuttal for Plaintiff as Side1:

Grantham v. Hodge and Carson v. DeWitt are distinguishable, since they

include the factor F4, which is not present in Smith.

In addition to the capabilities summarized above, the HYPO system included

algorithms for constructing hypothetical cases and making arguments using

hypotheticals.6 The theory of arguing with hypotheticals (Rissland 1985) was

based on identifying dimensions that could be manipulated (often by changing just

one aspect of the fact situation) to create a hypothetical case that could be used in

a legal argument.

Later systems extended the use of HYPO-style factors in several ways. In the

GREBE system, Branting (1991) developed a hierarchical representation of the

ratio decidendi of cases, which was used to apply portions of a prior cases holdings

to a new case, even when other portions of the prior case were not on-point. Brantings

model addressed a well-known weakness of the pure factor-based approach

to case-based reasoning: its failure to represent the reasoning that connects the

factors with the results of a case. The logic underlying a legal decision is implicitly

encoded in GREBE by grouping the factors of a precedent according to the

holdings they influence. In the CABARET system, Rissland and Skalak (1991)

described a mixed strategy for legal argumentation using both rules and cases.

Dimension-based analysis of precedents is one of the methods CABARET employs

to guide its selection of argument moves: the broadening of a rules interpretation,

the discrediting of a rule, or some other strategy.

Legal reasoning models that combine rules and cases include (Gardner 1987), in

which cases were used to handle the problem of open-textured concepts legal concepts

that do not have clear definitions to determine their applicability, but which

depend on experience and common sense, such as the concept of recklessness.

Gardner used a decision tree to model the application of legal rules to a case,

with the leaves representing either factual predicates that could be observed, or

open-textured concepts. The open-textured leaves were linked to cases comprising

positive and negative examples. Other approaches to combining rules and cases

include Groendijk and Oskamp (1993) and Vossos et al. (1991). The issue-case

discrimination trees described by Hafner (1987) combine legal rules with cases in

a conceptual retrieval system.

The use of fact-based dimensions to evaluate the relevance of precedents, as

exemplified by HYPO, GREBE, CABARET and other systems (Cuthill and Mc-

26 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Cartney 1994) appears to be well-suited to modeling legal reasoning in common

law jurisdictions, since the rule of stare decisis applies in these jurisdictions. However,

despite the important role of fact similarity, the application of stare decisis,

as understood by skillful attorneys and applied by the courts, is both more complex

and less absolute than can be accurately described using fact similarity alone.

3. Teleological context: Modeling the purposes of legal concepts

In this section, we examine the teleological aspects of case-based legal reasoning:

the purposes and policies that often determine which precedents are found to be

most relevant, and which of several competing precedents will be followed. While

the need for teleological structure in rule-based systems has previously been noted

by Smith and Deedman (1987), their deep structure model of purposes did not

stipulate any necessary correspondence to the doctrines or concepts articulated in

judicial opinions (op. cit., p. 87). In contrast, below we propose a model of legal

purposes in case-based legal reasoning systems that is based on the teleological

arguments actually made (or likely to be made) by skilled advocates. Thus, we

model teleological context in order to provide support for legal argument moves,

as described in Rissland (1985).

3.1. THE ROLE OF TELEOLOGY IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING

From their first day at U.S. law schools, students learn that the relevance of facts

cannot be divorced from the purposes behind legal rules. Consider the following

three cases, which are studied by many American law students. In Pierson v. Post7

the plaintiff was fox hunting on open public land. While the plaintiff with horse and

hound pursued the fox, the defendant well knowing the fox was so hunted . . . did,

in the sight of Post, to prevent his catching the same, kill and carry it off. The

Court ruled that in order to recover, the plaintiff had to have gained possession of

the fox. In ruling that the plaintiff had not gained possession, which would require

either capturing the fox or mortally wounding it, the Court explained:

[We so hold] for the sake of certainty, and preserving peace and order in

society. If the first seeing, starting, or pursuing such animals . . . should afford

the basis of actions . . . itwould prove a fertile source of quarrels and litigation.

The Court articulated a vision that, if they did not establish strict guidelines for

obtaining title to wild animals, they might be swamped with disgruntled hunters

arguing over who first saw the animal.

A dissenting judge, in an effort to justify a contrary result, argued:

When we reflect . . . that the interest of our husbandmen, the most useful of

men in any community, will be advanced by the destruction of a beast so

pernicious and incorrigible, we cannot err in saying that a pursuit like the

present . . . confers . . . a right to the object of it.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 27

The dissenter had the vision of many additional foxes ravaging local farms unless

hunters are protected in their pursuits.

Since factual characterization takes place within a broad philosophical and jurisprudential

context, judges may not adhere to a uniform definition of possession in

all wild animal cases. Given the dissenters justification, he might have agreed with

the majoritys result had the hunter been pursuing a quail rather than a fox. Similarly,

the majority might have reached a contrary decision were violence among

sportsmen a frequent result of such confrontational behavior.

Students next read Keeble v. Hickeringill.8 There the plaintiff owned a duck

pond upon which he placed duck decoys. The defendant, intending to injure the

plaintiffs livelihood, used guns to scare away the ducks. Even though the plaintiff

had neither wounded nor captured the ducks, the Court found for the plaintiff by

reasoning,

[W]here a violent or malicious act is done to a mans occupation, profession

or way of getting a livelihood, there an action lies in all cases. But if a man

doth him damage by using the same employment; as if Mr. Hickeringill had

set up another decoy on his own ground near the plaintiffs, and that had

spoiled the custom of the plaintiff, no action would lie . . . This is like the case

of 11 H. 4,47. One schoolmaster sets up a new school to the damage of an

antient school, thereby the scholars are allured from the old school to come to

his new. (The action was held there not to lie.) But suppose Mr. Hickeringill

should lie in the way with his guns, and fright the boy from going to school

. . . sure that schoolmaster might have action . . .

***

And when . . . decoy[s] have been used . . . in order to be taken for profit

of the owner of the pond . . . and whereby the markets of the nation may be

furnished; there is great reason to give encouragement thereunto . . .

Once the purpose of the rule is understood, analogous cases setting forth the right

of school-masters become more relevant than cases dealing with foxes.

In dealing with these cases, law students also develop the ability to isolate and

match the relevant factors. Obvious similarities exist between Pierson and Keeble:

both cases involved unfettered wild animals, and both involved defendants motivated

by malice. However, students easily distinguish Pierson from Keeble on the

grounds that the plaintiff in Pierson was hunting the fox on open land while the

plaintiff in Keeble set out the decoys on his own land, and the plaintiff in Pierson

was hunting for sport while the plaintiff in Keeble was pursuing his livelihood.

The importance of this type of symbolic matching becomes evident when the

students move to an examination of Young v. Hitchens.9 In Young, the plaintiff,

a commercial fisherman, spread a net of 140 fathoms in length across a portion

of open ocean. After the plaintiff had closed the net to a space of a few fathoms,

the defendant went through the opening and spread its net and caught the fish.

Students, focusing on the plaintiffs need to make a living, match to Keeble, which

would portend a plaintiffs victory. Students also map to the open land in Pierson

28 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Figure 3. Factors and claim lattice in wild animal domain.

which suggests that the defendant should prevail. In Young, the court found for the

defendant.

Figure 3 shows the relevant factors in the wild animal domain, and the relationship

among the three cases based on those factors, following the HYPO framework

described in Section 2. This data structure can be used to generate a 3-ply argument

of the type described in Ashley (1990, pp. 7071):

Argument I.

Point for Defendant

Where: Plaintiff was seeking capture of a wild animal and did not mortally

wound or capture the animal, the defendant should win a claim for trespass.

Cite: Pierson v. Post. The open land in Pierson is like the open sea in the

current case.

Response for Plaintiff

Pierson is distinguishable because in Pierson the plaintiff did not make his

living from capture of wild animals.

Counterexample:

Keeble v. Hickeringill held for the plaintiff even though the plaintiff was

seeking to capture wild animals, and did not mortally wound or capture the

animals.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 29

Rebuttal for Defendant

Keeble is distinguishable because in Keeble the plaintiff was conducting his

business on his own land.

Keeble is also distinguishable because in Keeble the defendant was acting

maliciously while here the defendant was engaged in business competition.

Though accurately transcribing many law school class discussions, the model is

incomplete because at some point the student must answer the question which

precedent should govern and why? Even though attorneys wield their adversarial

foils with considerable dexterity, judges, when studying legal arguments, do not

act as referees at an intellectual fencing match. Rather, they make rules that significantly

affect human lives and their decisions necessarily embody their views

(or prejudices) as to which rules improve the quality of life in society. Therefore,

lawyers, in addition to arguments based on factors, must suggest to judges persuasive

policy arguments for choosing the side they represent. Here are some of the

teleological (i.e., policy) arguments that the court probably considered in Young,

reconstructed from the reported opinion10

Argument II:

Point for Defendant

You should apply the rule of Pierson because the uncertainty about what constitutes

property rights to fish swimming in the open sea will cause endless

controversy.

Response for Plaintiff

You should apply the rule of Keeble because it is important that people earn

a living and the defendant has interfered with the plaintiffs ability to make a

living.

Rebuttal for Defendant

Keeble is distinguishable because the defendant in Keeble was acting maliciously,

while here the defendant was merely engaged in vigorous competition

like the schoolmaster who sets up a competing school. Society benefits from

such competition.

Surrebuttal for Plaintiff

Society permits vigorous competition but not unfair competition. The actions

of the defendant will force the plaintiff to take wasteful actions to protect his

catches when the defendant could be pursuing other fish, which would increase

the amount of fish available to consumers.

30 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Surrebuttal for Defendant

Guidelines for determining whether competition among fishermen is fair or unfair

should be left to the legislature, otherwise there could be endless lawsuits

attempting to establish what fishermen may or may not do.

Lord Denmans opinion in Young indicates that he was moved by the plaintiffs

argument, but denied relief because of a procedural error.11 Judge Pattesons

concurring opinion suggests that he was influenced by the thrust of defendants

surrebuttal. It would appear that Judge Wightmans concurring opinion accepted

the endless quarrels rationale.

3.2. A COMPUTATIONAL MODEL OF TELEOLOGICAL CONTEXT

To develop an adequate model of legal purposes and their role in legal reasoning

is one of the long-term goals of the AI and Law field; in this paper, we take a

small step in that direction. We show how to make a case-based reasoning system

a little smarter by attaching some information about the purposes involved in its

case knowledge base. To do this, we consider what these purposes are, how they

are related to each other in the domain of interest, and how they can be used within

the framework of case-based legal reasoning and argument.

Discovering the relevant legal purposes in a domain is the goal (along with finding

the relevant authorities and identifying the relevant factors) of a skillful legal

researcher. By reading judicial opinions and consulting appropriate commentary, it

is possible (although sometimes difficult) to understand what purposes the courts

are trying to advance. Our approach to discovering purposes in a legal domain will

be the same one used to discover factors or dimensions in the HYPO-style systems

described in Section 2. That is, a knowledge engineering approach is used, where

the human expert determines what concepts to include in a domain model. For

the wild animal examples, the purposes we will discuss are those mentioned in

Argument II above:

to define possession in a way that promotes certainty and discourages

lawsuits;

to protect a persons livelihood from interference;

to protect free enterprise and competition;

for the judiciary to respect the powers of the legislature;

to protect the rights of property owners;

to protect the rights of all citizens to use and enjoy public lands.

Many if not most interesting legal cases involve some underlying teleological

issues, and in order to fully appreciate these issues, it is necessary to understand

how different legal purposes are related to each other. There are several types of

relationships among legal purposes, which are illustrated in Figure 4, including two

adversarial relations (c and d):

a. the taxonomic relation (ISA) relates a general purpose, such as the achievement

of certainty and predictability in the law, to a more specific one, such

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 31

Figure 4. Knowledge structure for legal purposes.

as the unambiguous definition of what it means to be in possession of a wild

animal. This ISA relation also connects the general purpose of encouraging

useful activities to the more specific ones of encouraging fox hunting, duck

hunting, and fishing.

b. the instrumental relation (INST) relates a general purpose to a purpose that

contributes to achieving it (thus, SUPP is a causal link). For example, assuming

there is a general goal of promoting economic welfare of citizens, a more

specific goal that supports this is the protection of a persons livelihood from

interference.

c. a limitation relation (LIMIT) expresses the situation where the degree to which

one purpose can be pursued is limited by another purpose. For example, the

personal freedom of individuals is limited by the prohibition against doing

harm to others; the exercise of the right of free speech is limited by the purpose

of protecting the public from obscenity; and in the wild animal example, the

purpose of preventing unfair competition imposes a limit on the purpose of

protecting free enterprise.

d. a relationship of direct opposition (OPP) sometimes exists between pairs of

legal purposes in the extreme case, for each purpose advanced by one side

of a legal dispute, there is a competing and equally worthy purpose advanced

by the other side. The adversarial structure of legal argument can be analyzed

in terms of such competing purposes. (Kennedy, 1991, p. 101) Figure 4 shows

three pairs of opposing purposes:

32 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

i. certainty of legal rules competes with context sensitivity (for example, the

need for consistency in criminal sentencing competing with the need to

consider each individual defendants circumstances);

ii. protection of livelihood competes with protection of economic competition;

iii. prevention of unfairness by the courts competes with respect for legislative

prerogatives.

Note that the structure of legal purposes shown in Figure 4 (and legal argument

II, which is derived from the Young opinion) leads to argument points that were

not explicitly raised in the earlier wild animal cases points involving unfair competition

and judicial/legislative competency. Teleological knowledge allows a legal

reasoning system to go beyond fact-based comparisons with precedents to include

these broader jurisprudential concepts.

There are several approaches that might be used to incorporate legal purposes

into the computational framework of legal case-based reasoning systems, as described

in Section 2. One could create knowledge structures that package the

reasoning underlying explanations [of cases] (Schank and Leake 1990, p. 354).

Such explanations might constitute a slot in a case frame and these slots could be

indexed in numerous ways to retrieve both similar and analogous cases. So the

explanation of Pierson might be not-possession to avoid unnecessary disputes

while the explanation of Keeble might be possession to protect the plaintiffs

livelihood. Such a scheme would have problems, since the explanations would

need to be broken up and recombined when only some of the dimensions of the

current case match the prior case, as is done in the GREBE system (Branting 1991),

which combines partial arguments from several prior cases.

We have chosen a different scheme, illustrated in Figure 5, which utilizes the

factor-based model of case-based legal reasoning, but adds teleological knowledge

to it. Prior systems using the factor-based approach (described in Section 2) have

encoded each factor as either favorable to the plaintiff or favorable to the defendant.

A limitation of this approach is the lack of explanatory power as to why a factor

favors the plaintiff or defendant, and why that factor is legally relevant. In our

scheme, each factor is linked to the legal purpose(s) which it affects, and each legal

purpose in turn specifies whether it favors the plaintiff or defendant. Finally, each

legal purpose is linked to other purposes that may compete with it (adversarial

Links), so that the case-based reasoning system knows when purpose A is advanced,

that purpose B may be endangered, providing a foundation for making

policy arguments such as those we have illustrated above.

3.3. IMPLICATIONS FOR FUTURE SYSTEMS

Using the knowledge representations proposed here, a system for case-based legal

reasoning would generate several sophisticated types of arguments. For the Young

case discussed in Section 4.1, an argument can be generated that resembles Argu-

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 33

Figure 5. Incorporating legal purposes into case analysis structure.

Figure 6. Teleological representation of wild animal cases.

34 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

ment II more than Argument I. In Argument I, the defendant points out that the fish

had not been captured or mortally wounded, just as in Pierson. However, using the

knowledge representation for the wild animal domain shown in Figures 4 and 6, an

argument can be created whose first steps would be:

Point for Defendant

This case is like Pierson v. Post, since the plaintiff did not capture or mortally

wound the fish. It is important to define possession in a way that promotes

certainty and avoids unnecessary disputes.

Response for Plaintiff

This case can be distinguished from Pierson v. Post, since in that case the

plaintiff did not make his living from the hunting of wild animals.

This case is more like Keeble v. Hickeringill, since in that case the plaintiff was

prevented from pursuing his livelihood. It is important to protect people who

are pursuing their livelihood, since productive work benefits society.

Rebuttal for Defendant

This case can be distinguished from Keeble, since in Keeble the interference

was not done for economic competition, while in this case the defendant was

merely competing vigorously with the plaintiff. The law should not discourage

free enterprise and competition.

In distinguishing a case (as the plaintiff in Youngmay attempt to do), the adversarial

link from certainty to encourage useful enterprise can be used to help the casebased

reasoner create policy arguments. For example, the plaintiff in Young might

bolster his response by stressing the importance of fishing as a more useful activity

than fox hunting:

Response for Plaintiff (additional point)

If fishermen who spread their nets must bear the additional risk that anyone can

come along and take the fish out of the net, this will hurt our economy. Fishing

will become such a risky occupation that people will avoid it altogether.

The limitations of this scheme are several: first, the policies motivating a legal rule

may change due to a shift in societys values or a change in other social institutions

(such as insurance) that make existing rules unnecessary. (In Section 4, we explore

this limitation and propose further computational mechanisms for overcoming it.)

Second, attorneys and courts conceive and express purposes at varying levels of

abstraction. An advocate for the defendant in Young v. Hitchens who believed

that a judge (possibly influenced by the law and economics movement) would be

persuaded by policies based on maximizing market efficiency might argue:

Point for Defendant

The defendant should win because this type of competition will encourage the

most efficient methods for trapping fish.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 35

Or, believing that a judge (possibly influenced by the work of critical legal theorists)

would be persuaded by arguments based on the inequities resulting from the

influence of large corporations, the attorney for the defendant might argue:

Point for Defendant

The defendant should win because protecting the plaintiff is protecting established

big business interests at the expense of smaller entrepreneurs.

Though incomplete, the arsenal of teleological arguments described here more

closely approximates real world advocacy in common law jurisdictions than those

produced by case-based reasoning models that do not include a representation of

legal purposes. Although our model is far from being able to replicate the full range

of teleological argument moves employed by a gifted attorney, we anticipate that

case-based legal reasoning systems incorporating even limited teleological knowledge

will prove useful both for legal practice systems and for computer-assisted

legal education (Aleven and Ashley 1994).

The representation framework developed in this Section also points the way

toward a model of legal reasoning capable of recognizing and exploiting analogies

between different legal domains, such as wild-animal hunting and education. By

representing knowledge about the competing legal purposes at stake in a case such

as Keeble, the relevance of analogous cases involving the same competing purposes

(such as the hypothetical case of two competing schools (11 H. 4) distinguished

by the court in Keeble) can be recognized. In the next Section, we also consider

the potential of teleological structures to support analogies between cases decided

under different legal doctrines (e.g., contract and tort).

4. Temporal context: Modeling the evolution of legal doctrine

In this section we consider a second aspect of context that profoundly affects the

reasoning of lawyers and judges about previously-decided cases: their relationship

to other, more recently decided cases. We demonstrate that legal precedents are

embedded in a temporal context of evolving legal doctrine, which can result in a

strong precedent becoming weaker over time, to the point where a skillful attorney

could reasonably predict that it will no longer be followed. We propose computational

mechanisms that would permit such trends in judicial thinking to be taken

into account in a case-based legal reasoning system.

Similar processes of change occur in science, and many readers will notice

similarities between the evolution of legal doctrine described here and the process

of change in scientific theories described by Kuhn (1970). The desirability

of giving greater weight to more recent decisions (Ashley and Rissland 1987) and

utilizing legal doctrine to assess relevance has been noted by others (Branting 1994,

Rissland et al. 1996). However, to date no one has attempted to represent precisely

and computationally the methods used by lawyers to assess the continuing strength

of legal precedents over time.

36 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

The standard approach to legal case-based reasoning selects precedents by comparing

each prior case to the current fact situation, and preferring the prior case(s)

that are most similar. Unfortunately, this approach does not take into account how

a prior case has been treated by other (more recent) prior cases, which may change

the picture radically. Such temporal analysis of case law to recognize evolving

legal doctrine is taught from the first year of law school; case-based models of

legal reasoning would be much improved by incorporating even limited abilities

for temporal analysis of a case knowledge base.

In Section 4.1, we analyze a series of cases from New York to show how the

territorial view in conflict of laws was gradually eroded and finally overturned

between 1945 and 1963. Our problem scenario involves a passenger who is injured

in an automobile accident, and later sues the driver for negligence in a state other

than the one where the accident occurred. The conflict of laws issue is whether

to apply the substantive law of the place where the accident occurred (the situs)

or the place where the case is being litigated (the forum) regarding the liability of

drivers to passengers. In Section 4.2 we identify patterns of legal reasoning that

occur over a series of cases, and consider how a skillful attorney might recognize

these patterns and reasonably predict that a precedent which was once strong will

no longer be followed.

In Section 4.3 we propose further extensions to the extended case knowledge

base structures described in Section 3, which could support the kind of legal reasoning

observed in the New York conflict cases. In Section 4.4 we introduce an

algorithm for evaluating the precedential strength of a prior case in its temporal

context, and consider the implications of this kind of analysis for case-based legal

reasoning and argumentation.

4.1. GUEST PASSENGERS: AN EXAMPLE OF EVOLVING LEGAL DOCTRINE

What follows is a summary of a series of New York cases dealing with the right

of a guest passenger in an automobile to sue a host driver when both the driver

and passenger reside in New York, the car is registered and ensured in New York,

and the accident takes place in a jurisdiction (other than New York) where a statute

limits the guest passengers right to sue the driver.

Two considerations led some jurisdictions to adopt guest passenger statutes

which are exceptions to the generally accepted policy that injured victims should

receive compensation for injuries resulting from the defendants negligent behavior.

First, some jurisdictions like Ontario, Canada evidently felt that if the host

does the guest a favor by providing transportation, gratitude demands that the guest

not sue the host for the hosts negligence. This would explain Ontarios absolute

bar to such law suits.12 Other jurisdictions evidently believed that too often the

guest passenger and the host driver (perhaps good friends or relatives) colluded

to defraud the defendants insurance carrier. Some states, such as Montana and

Virginia, adopted statutes requiring a showing of gross negligence in order for the

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 37

guest to recover, which would require a host driver to admit to engaging in conduct

that could lead to a loss of license or criminal sanctions.

Our problem case is Babcock v. Jackson.13 Babcock and Jackson were both

residents of New York, the guest-host relationship had been formed in New York,

and a few hours after their trip began in New York, Jackson lost control of his car

in Ontario, Canada. Babcock was injured and in 1961 sued in a New York court

alleging negligence in the operation of the vehicle. New York law would allow

Babcock to recover on a mere showing that Jackson drove negligently.

A straightforward matching with prior cases would lead an attorney to conclude

that the law of Ontario applies and therefore the plaintiff loses. In 1938 New Yorks

highest court in Smith v. Clute14 had to decide whether the Montana guest statutes

applied to New York residents traveling through Montana on their way to California.

The court held that the accident occurred in Montana, and the law of that state

governed the plaintiffs right of action. However, the court found for the plaintiff

anyway, holding that because the guest had contributed money toward the expenses

of the trip, he did not meet the criteria of a guest passenger according to Montana

law.

Seven years later in Kerfoot v. Kelley,15 the intermediate court of appeals in

New York made a similar determination of applicability of Virginia law, finding for

the defendant in a case of wrongful death resulting from an automobile accident.

In both Smith and Kerfoot, the guest passenger law required a showing of gross

negligence in order for the guest to recover. Thus, in 1945 a practitioner would

predict that Babcock had a losing case. In fact, all cases involving guest passengers

in New York from 1945 until 1963 left little doubt that the law of the state in which

the accident occurred governed the case.16

The decisions in Smith and Kerfoot were based on the traditional territorial

choice of law doctrine that applies the law of the place where the events that gave

rise to the dispute occurred. The justification for the territorial rule was to assure

that a case will be treated the same way regardless of whether the plaintiff brought

the case in New York or Montana. Applying the rules of law irrespective of the

forum appears fairer because the rights of the parties do not depend on which state

decides the case. In legal parlance, the territorial view minimizes the advantages of

forum shopping. Another rationale for the territorial rule is based on the principle

that parties should be subject to predictable laws. A visitor to Montana understands

and implicitly agrees that while in Montana he is subject to the laws of that state.

In the 1940s this territorial theory of conflict of laws had been applied by the

highest courts of New York to most choice of law cases. In 1959 the highest court

of New York in Kaufman v. American Youth Hostels17 decided that an Oregon law

that immunized charities from tort liability barred a wrongful death suit by a New

York plaintiff against a New York defendant who died in a mountain climbing

accident in Oregon. Therefore, even a New York practitioner who took a somewhat

broader view of relevant cases would probably predict that Ontario law would

apply since the accepted rule in New York in 1962 was that "the substantive rights

38 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

and liabilities arising out of a tortious occurrence are determinable by the law of

the place of the wrong (Babcock, p. 473)

However, the territorial rule had been subject to much scholarly criticism based

primarily on the fact that the territorial view of conflict of laws did not take into

account the social policies underlying the substantive law of the concerned jurisdictions

(Babcock, footnotes 3 and 4). The policies behind these statutes were

either to protect hosts from ungrateful guests or to prevent fraud on insurance

companies. But these policies would not apply to a case where both the plaintiff and

defendant are from New York, a state that believes the potential for ingratitude or

fraud does not outweigh the policy of compensation for injured plaintiffs. A simple

hypothetical example demonstrates why so many legal scholars criticized the territorial

rule. If the plaintiff in Babcock were injured several feet before crossing

into Ontario, then the plaintiff recovers and New Yorks policy of compensation

would be fulfilled; but if the accident took place several minutes later after the

parties had crossed into Ontario, then the plaintiff loses and the New York policy of

compensation would be thwarted without furthering any interest of Ontario, since

the defendant was from New York.

A knowledgeable attorney would have appreciated that the New York courts

had begun to question the territorial rule in areas other than personal injury law.

In 1954 New Yorks highest court in Auten v. Auten18 abandoned the territorial

approach in the field of contracts. Under the territorial doctrine, the law governing

contracts required that matters concerned with validity be governed by the law

where the contract was executed (in this case, New York) while matters related to

performance were governed by the law where the contract was to be performed

(mostly England). Rather than rely on this traditional view, in Auten the court,

interpreting a child support agreement, adopted a center of gravity rule, holding

that the execution of the agreement in New York was merely fortuitous and the

most important contacts like the marriage, separation, and domicile of the wife and

children were in England.

Though representing a partial rejection of the territorial rule, Auten could not

be relied upon by an attorney trying a case in the area of personal injury. First, the

opinion made clear that the same result would have been reached had the territorial

rule been utilized, since the issue involved the wifes performance and that performance

occurred in England. Thus, the articulation of a new legal doctrine could

be seen as merely dictum. Secondly, and more to the point, Auten had been decided

five years prior to 1959 when the highest court of New York decided Kaufman,

which affirmed the territorial rule in the area of tort law.

In May of 1961 the New York court decided Haag v. Barnes,19 which affirmed

the center of gravity approach adopted in Auten in an area of law similar to Auten.

After Haag, an attorney could reasonably conclude that a paradigm shift had occurred

in choice of law in the field of contracts. This, in combination with the

scholarly criticism of the territorial rule in tort law, might engender a prediction

that a similar paradigm shift would eventually take place in torts as well. Kilberg v.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 39

Northeast Airlines,20 decided in January 1961, provided evidence to support such

a prediction. Kilberg, while in the state of New York, purchased a ticket to fly from

New York to Massachusetts. Kilberg died when the plane crashed in Nantucket,

Massachusetts. A Massachusetts statute limited the damages from wrongful death

to $15,000, while New York had no such limit. Under the territorial rule, the Massachusetts

law would govern. However, the court ignored the precedents and held

that the Massachusetts wrongful death statute applied to the question of whether

the plaintiff had a right to sue, but that New York law applied as to the amount of

damages the plaintiff could recover.

Four of the seven judges, while not rejecting the territorial rule, invoked exceptions

to the general rule that the law of the place of the wrong would apply. The

court relied primarily on the public policy exception:

Modern conditions make it unjust and anomalous to subject the traveling citizen

of this State to the varying laws of other States through and over which

they move. An air traveler from New York may in a flight of a few hours

duration pass through several . . . commonwealths. His plane may meet with

disaster in a State he never intended to cross but into which the plane has flown

because of bad weather or other unexpected developments . . . The place of

injury becomes entirely fortuitous. Our courts should if possible provide protection

for our own States people against unfair and anachronistic treatment

of the lawsuits which result from these disasters. (Kilberg, p. 34)

Two judges, though concurring with the result on procedural grounds, rejected the

majoritys analysis:

Questions relating to such defenses as contributory (comparative) negligence

. . . charitable immunity . . . incapacity of wife to sue . . . have all been regarded

by this court as regulated by the law of the place of injury rather than our own

law . . . In each of these cases we applied a foreign rule although such rule was

clearly contrary to the law of our own State . . . The majority would apply our

own law of damages because the place of injury is entirely fortuitous. The

same argument may be made with respect to each of the cases just referred to.

We should not overrule well-established principles . . . The position adopted

by the majority may result in the situation where, in a single airplane crash

in which numerous passengers from various States are killed, a different law

will be applied in each action resulting therefrom. (Kilberg, p. 71)

Although Kilberg did not explicitly reject the territorial rule, it represents an implicit

paradigm shift that casts doubt on the rule. An attorney reading Kilberg (a tort

case) in combination with Auten and Haag might reasonably predict that the New

York court was ready to extend the new choice of law theory to tort law in general.

This is precisely what occurred in Babcock, where the court held for the plaintiff,

rejecting the territorial view in favor of the center of gravity approach (also called

grouping of contacts) which the court had adopted in Auten:

40 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Comparison of the relative contacts and interests of New York and Ontario

in this litigation, vis--vis the issue here presented, makes it clear that the

concern of New York is unquestionably the greater . . . The present action

involves injuries sustained by a New York guest as the result of the negligence

of a New York host in the operation of an automobile, garaged, licensed and

undoubtedly insured in New York, in the course of a week-end journey which

began and was to end there. In sharp contrast, Ontarios sole relationship

with the occurrence is the purely adventitious circumstance that the accident

occurred there. (Babcock, p. 458)

4.2. TEMPORAL PATTERNS SIGNIFYING A WEAKENING OF PRECEDENT

How would the attorney in Babcock predict that the on-point and formerly solid

precedents of Smith, Kerfoot and Kaufman might not be followed? We have identified

five temporal patterns of judicial behavior which could lead a skillful attorney

to that prediction (ordered from the strongest evidence to the weakest):

1. If the precedent is explicitly over-ruled, the prediction that it will not be followed

in the future is an obvious (although far from certain) consequence.

However, the frequency of explicit over-ruling is low compared to other signs

of weakening.

2. A precedent is implicitly over-ruled when the result in a newer case clearly

contradicts an older case with very similar facts, even if the court does not

explicitly say the prior case is over-ruled. For example, one can argue that

Babcock, once decided, implicitly over-ruled Kerfoot, and Kilberg implicitly

over-ruled earlier cases which applied the situs limitations on wrongful death

claims made by New York residents.

3. The ratio decidendi of an older case has been over-ruled, even though the

facts may differ in significant respects. For example, in explicitly rejecting

the territorial view in favor of the center of gravity view, one can argue that

Babcock over-rules Kaufman, even though Kaufman was not a guest passenger

case.

4. A shift in the relative priority of competing purposes is in evidence from the

courts tendency to make a rule increasingly narrow by finding exceptions and

distinguishing away situations where one might have expected the rule to

apply. The finding of a public policy exception in Kilberg can be viewed in

this light, suggesting that the court was straining for reasons to avoid applying

the territorial rule.

5. A general shift in the relative priority of competing purposes is in evidence

from cases from other legal domains. The Auten and Haag cases, coming from

the contracts domain, could provide evidence that the purposes advanced by

the territorial rule were losing ground to the competing purposes advanced by

the center-of-gravity rule. Babcock extended this shift to the guest passenger

domain.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 41

Table I. Case knowledge base for guest passenger cases

Smith v. Klute (1938) Kerfoot v. Kelley (1945)

Result: Passenger wins (Side1) Result: Host wins (Side2)

Relevant Factors Relevant Factors

Claim: driver negligence Claim:Driver Negligence

Same-residence: yes Same-residence: yes

Relationship-loc: forum Relationship-loc: forum

Non-forum-law-limits-recovery: yes Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes

Basis of limits: gross-negl-standard Basis of denial: gross-negl-standard

Passenger is guest: no Passenger is guest: yes

Factor Purpose served Favors

Claim:driver negligence PD Side1

Same-residence: yes PB Side1

Relationship-loc: forum PB Side1

Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes PA Side2

Basis of denial: gross-negl-standard PC Side2

Passenger is guest: {yes, no} {PC, PD} {Side2, Side1}

PA = Territorial Rule (law should be determined by location of events giving rise to the dispute);

PB = Center of Gravity Rule (law should be determined by location of parties overall

relationship); PC = Avoid fraudulent claims; PD = Compensate accident victims.

Figure 7a. Legal purposes for choice of law doctrines.

42 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Figure 7b. Legal purposes for guest passenger preclusion statues.

In the next two sections, we consider how these patterns can be recognized and

taken into account by a case-based legal reasoning system. (A possible sixth pattern

signifying legal change would be the existence of a substantial scholarly attack on

a given legal doctrine; however our model of case-based reasoning does not include

recognizing trends in the scholarly literature.)

4.3. A COMPUTATIONAL MODEL OF TEMPORAL CONTEXT

In this Section, we consider how a case-based legal reasoning model can support

the kind of legal analysis that can explain, and possibly predict, the results in the

New York conflicts cases. The jumping-off point for our analysis is the model of

teleological case-based reasoning proposed in Section 3. In that model, we extended

the HYPO-style factor comparison model described in Section 2, by linking

each judicially-recognized factor in a legal domain to one or more legal purposes

or policies that define its raison detre. The various legal purposes were in turn

organized into a semantic net, with links representing both supporting and competing

relations between pairs of purposes. Whereas in the factor comparison model

the computation of relevance was based on which prior cases had a maximal set of

shared factors with the current case, in our model prior cases could also be found

relevant if they involved the same structure of competing purposes, even if they

shared few (or even no) domain-specific factors.

Applying this approach in a straightforward way to the guest-passenger cases,

we can create a network of legal purposes as shown in Figure 7, and index the Smith

and Kerfoot cases as shown in Table I. Figure 7a shows a legal policy network in

the choice of law domain: at the lowest level, the policy that says a dispute should

be resolved using the law of the location of the events that gave rise to the dispute

competes with the policy that says avoid applying laws of a jurisdiction that plays

only a fortuitous role in the dispute and has little or no interest in the outcome.

Figure 7b shows competing purposes in the torts domain that are directly relevant

to guest passenger statutes the accepted legal policy of compensating victims of

negligence vs. the states desire to minimize fraudulent claims.

Table I shows how Smith and Kerfoot would be presented using the teleological

case representation developed in Section 3. (Side 1 in all examples is the party

whose recovery or compensation is limited by the non-forum law e.g., the guest

passenger.) Factors that might influence the court include whether the parties are

from the same state (other than the state where the accident occurred) and whether

the parties had a prior relationship formed outside of the state where the accident

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 43

occurred. If both of these factors are present, this makes the location of the accident

appear more fortuitous. Factors that affect the application of a statutory preclusion

(or limitation) of recovery include whether the guest passenger has paid something

to the driver (and was therefore not completely gratuitous) and whether the claim

before the court is one to which the preclusion can apply.

In considering Smith and Kerfoot as precedents for Babcock, we immediately

see that the relevant holding is not the final result of the case but rather the intermediate

holding of whether to apply New York law or the law of the situs.

Although different sides won in these two cases, as precedents for Babcock they

are on the same side they would both be precedents for the defendant. As Branting

(1991) has pointed out, most cases have several holdings which depend on

different subsets of the relevant factors, and which can be used as precedents even

in cases where factors outside the relevant subset do not match. In a later paper,

Branting (1994) presented a formal definition of the ratio decidendi of cases, and

showed that the precedential significance of a case cannot be understood without

considering the ratio as well as the facts and the final result.

Therefore we propose to extend our case knowledge base design in the following

way: we define the results of a case as the set of all holdings that are part

of the ratio as defined by Branting. The extended results are represented in a slot-

filler structure, so that in guest passenger cases the winning-side slot would have

fillers guest or host while the apply-forum-law slot would have fillers yes or

no. With this extension, we can represent the relevance of cases such as Kaufman

and Kilberg to guest passenger cases such as Smith and Kerfoot.

However, we are still not satisfied with this characterization of the results of a

case as the set of all holdings, because it does not mention the territoriality doctrine

that was criticized in Kilberg and finally rejected in favor of the center-of-gravity

doctrine in Babcock. It is difficult to say that we have represented the result

of Babcock if we do not include this aspect of the case, since it weakens every

earlier precedent that cites the territorial rule as part of its ratio. To make the

representation more accurate we need to include a representation of the legal rules

used by a court to justify its holdings. In so doing, we are not intending to model

the process of rule application, but merely to include a reference to the legal rules

cited by the court, as one of the attributes on which cases can be compared. For

the sample cases, we will add a result slot: rules-followed, whose fillers include

territorial and center-of-gravity. (Note: after Babcock, this simple story of

two competing doctrines was complicated by the rejection of the center-of-gravity

doctrine in Tooker v. Lopez21 in favor of a greater interest approach, but we will

not consider that distinction here.)

It is interesting to note that the two contracts cases that first rejected the territorial

rule failed to apply the law of the forum, finding instead that some other

jurisdiction was the center of gravity for the contractual relationships. Thus, as

in the case of Babcock, the correct interpretation of these cases by a case-based

44 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Table II. Extended case knowledge base for choice of law cases

Smith v. Klute (1938) Kerfoot v. Kelley (1938)

Holdings: Holdings:

Winning-side: passenger (Side1) Winning-side: driver/owner (Side2)

Forum-law-controls: no Forum-law-controls: no

Choice-of-law rule: territorial Choice-of-law-rule: territorial

Relevant factors: Relevant factors:

Claim: driver negligence Claim: driver negligence

Same-residence: yes Same-residence: yes

Relationship-loc: forum Relationship-loc: forum

Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes

Basis-of-limit: gross-negl-standard Basis-of-limit: gross-negl-standard

Trip-origin: forum Passenger-is-guest: yes

Length-of-non-forum-contact: brief

Passenger-is-guest: no

Auten v. Auten (1954) Haag v. Barnes (1961)

Holdings: Holdings:

Winning-side: Supported-spouse (Side1) Winning-side: Supporting-spouse (Side2)

Contract-upheld: yes Contract-upheld: yes

Forum-law-controls: no Forum-law-controls: no

Choice-of-law-rule: center-of-gravity Choice-of-law-rule: center-of-gravity

Relevant factors: Relevant Factors:

Claim: enforce support agreement Claim: reopen support agreement

Same-residence: unknown Same-residence: no

Relationship-loc: nonforum Relationship-loc: nonforum

Forum-law-limits-recovery: yes Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes

Basis of limit: contract Basis of limit: contract

Length of forum visit: brief Length of nonforum visit: months

Kaufman v. American Youth Hostels (1959) Kilberg v. Northeast Airlines (1961)

Holdings: Holdings:

Winning-side: Vendor (Side2) Winning-side: Passenger (Side1)

Forum-law-controls: no Forum-law-controls: yes

Choice-of-law-rule: territorial Choice-of-law-rule: public-policy overrides

territorial

Relevant Factors: Relevant Factors:

Claim: travel guide negligence Claim: common carrier negligence

Same-residence: yes Relationship-loc: forum

Relationship-loc: forum Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes

Nonforum-law-limits-recovery: yes Basis of limit: wrongful death damage limitation

Basis-of-limit: charitable immunity Trip-origin: forum

Length of nonforum visit: days Length of non-forum visit: brief

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 45

reasoning system requires the enunciated legal rules to be included in a cases

representation.

Table II shows the extended representation of the six previously-described cases

that the Babcock attorney might have considered. New factors introduced after

Kilberg include the length of time spent in the situs jurisdiction, and the place

where the trip originated. This information has been added to prior cases where it

can be determined from the written opinion.

4.4. INTEGRATING TEMPORAL CONTEXT INTO CASE-BASED LEGAL

REASONING: THE RED FLAG ALGORITHM

In this section, we consider how the temporal structure of legal decisions can be

used by a case-based reasoning system to influence the evaluation of relevance.

We assume there will be an initial comparison of the prior cases with the current

case based on the traditional factor-comparison model, and a similarity network for

on-point cases will be created. For each on-point case, we then create a temporallysequenced

list for each of the holdings of that case, containing later cases that had

holdings on the same issue. The list elements are labeled in a manner similar to the

treatments used in legal citators (i.e., followed, distinguished, criticized, over-ruled,

etc.) (cf. Ashley and Rissland 1987).

Using this structure, it is possible to evaluate, for the on-point cases from the

similarity network, the degree to which their holdings (on issues relevant to the

current case) have been weakened by subsequent cases. We now consider how a

case-based reasoning system should represent and calculate this weakening measure.

It is clear that temporal evaluation is a form of evidential reasoning, so we

propose a numerical measure of weakening ranging from 0 (no weakening) to

1 (complete over-rule). This value, like the numbers attached to conclusions in

expert systems, should be used for comparison purposes for example, although

the precise numbers are not very meaningful, assigning a weakening factor of 0.9

to a precedent indicates a high degree of risk to the party who relies on it.

We have considered two approaches to calculating the weakening factor: the

first approach is based on comparing the average age of cases that treated a precedent

positively with the average age of those that treated it negatively. A more

recent (i.e., lower) average age indicates more current doctrine. In considering the

details of such an algorithm, we concluded that this approach would pose signi-

ficant difficulties. One difficulty would arise when a decision pattern that has been

solidly entrenched for a long time has not been litigated very much in recent years,

but is still good law. For example, if the court had retreated from its reasoning in

Auten and reinstated the territorial rule (as would seem quite plausible in 1959 after

Kaufman was decided), the average age approach would not give a correct result,

since the cases that followed the territorial rule would be much older than Auten.

Another difficulty would arise when, in the course of a legal doctrine undergoing

change, the new doctrine is applied to one narrow sub-domain after another, and

46 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

eventually is accepted as a new general rule. If a recently-decided case happened to

be in a sub-domain where the change has not yet occurred, this would appear to be

a retreat from the new doctrine when it really is simply a characteristic of normal

evolution.

A different approach is based on the recognition of clues or red flags suggesting

that an established legal doctrine is under attack. When a legal decision either

refuses to follow prior cases (as in Kilberg) or explicitly rejects the ratio of prior

cases (as in Auten), this acts as a red flag that may lead a skillful attorney to question

whether the holdings of the prior cases (and others) that rely on the same legal rules,

will still be followed in the future. We have developed an algorithm based on this

conception of legal reasoning.

We define five types of red flag cases, corresponding to the five weakening

patterns described in Section 4.2. For a red flag of type i, we define a weakening

factor Wi between 0 and 1, representing the evidential strength supplied by that

type of red flag for the prediction that a precedent is no longer reliable. (The actual

values of theWi should be empirically determined; or they could be provided by the

user of a case-based reasoning system.) We use the traditional rule for combining

evidence in expert systems (Hayes-Roth et al. 1983): if there are two red flags

that weaken the same precedent P with weakening factors Wx and Wy , the overall

weakening of P would be calculated as Wx + Wy - (Wx . Wy).

An algorithm to compute the overall estimate of how much a holding H of

precedent P has been weakened by later cases C1, C2, . . . , is outlined below. The

algorithm is recursive: once a red flag case C has been identified, before its effect

on P can be estimated, the weakening of C itself by even later cases much be taken

into account.

RED FLAG ALGORITHM: Given a precedent P, a holding of P on an issue J ,

and a temporally-sequenced list of later cases that had holdings on the same issue,

compute the degree of weakening Wpj that Ps holding on issue J has undergone

since it was decided.

Step 1. Identify the red flags in the sequence of later cases (that is, later cases

providing evidence that Ps holding on issue J has been weakened).

Step 2. For each type of red flag i identified in Step 1:

i. Let C be the most recent case that is a red flag of type i.

ii. Compute (recursively) the weakening factor Wcj , based on even more recent

cases.

iii. Let the weakening effect of C on P (relative to issue J) be Wi . (1 - Wcj ).

Step 3. Combine the evidence from the various types of red flags, as computed in

Step 2.

Step 2 provides that if a precedent P applies the territorial rule, and the territorial

rule is weakened by a red flag case C, the later case may itself be weakened by a

return to the territorial rule subsequently. Assuming Wi is the weakening factor for

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 47

the type of red flag represented by C, if Wcj is close to zero indicating Cs holding

is still strong, the full weakening effect Wi of C will be applied to P. But if Wcj

is close to 1, indicating Cs holding has been eroded by second-order weakening,

then very little weakening will be applied to P on account of C.

If there are several red flag cases representing the same pattern, we use the most

recent one to stand in for the set. This approach has the advantage of simplicity:

when legal doctrines undergo change, it is not uncommon for decisions to shift

back and forth between the old approach and the new approach during a period

of great uncertainty. In those situations, an algorithm of this type would become

very inefficient if each red flag case were fully analyzed. By using the most recent

red flag of each type, we lose the ability to combine the influence of several similar

departures from the previously-established doctrine, but we gain the ability to focus

quickly on the end result.

The approach described here, in order to be implemented, requires additional

algorithms to identify the five types of red flag patterns. The first two patterns

could be readily identified by comparing the holdings of P with the holdings of

later decisions (assuming the case knowledge base is structured as described in

Section 4.3). The third pattern could also be readily identified, now that the results

of a case have been extended to include elements of the ratio. The fourth pattern,

in which new dimensions or rules are introduced to avoid following a precedent,

poses more difficulty, since we probably would not want to assume that every time

a case is distinguished, this represents a red flag.

The fifth pattern would be the most difficult to identify. In our example case

base, in order to predict that Auten and Haag weakened the precedents of Smith

and Kerfoot, it would be necessary first to find a connection between them, so that

the contracts cases could be included in the data being searched for red flags. One

possible approach to this problem is the following: whenever a case is decided

that breaks new ground, a marker is inserted into the network of legal purposes

indicating a shift in priorities between two competing purposes. Since each holding

of a case is identified with the legal purposes advanced by that holding, such

markers can be retrieved during Step 1 of the Red Flag Algorithm. This still leaves

a question, however, about how to relate the holding of the analogous case to the

holding in the area of interest. In the choice of law domain, this would not be

difficult since both domains invoke a territorial rule. However, this would not

always be true, and further study is needed to understand how results are used

analogously across domains, whether for supporting or weakening a precedent.

4.5. IMPLICATIONS FOR FUTURE SYSTEMS

The prospect of adding temporal analysis to a case-based legal reasoning system

gives rise to a number of questions, the most important being: how would a model

such as we have proposed affect the overall operation of a case-based legal argumentation

system? We can see two ways in which the use of weakening factors

48 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

could be used to improve the quality of arguments generated: first, if there are

several equally on-point cases (a frequent occurrence when a HYPO-style similarity

network is used), the system can present an argument based on the strongest

precedent first. Second, a new argument move can be developed to discredit a

precedent used by the opposing side, based on the claim that the precedent has

been weakened by subsequent decisions.

The evolution of legal doctrine that we illustrate above using the choice of law

domain is widespread within common law legal systems. In the United States it

can be found in the evolution of personal injury law from a negligence standard

toward strict liability; in the evolution of landlord and tenant law from a property

conveyancing doctrine to a contract law doctrine; in the evolution of contract law

from a paradigm of offer-and-acceptance toward the treatment of some cases under

a theory of promissory estoppel; and in the evolution of real-estate law toward

the imposition of new duties of disclosure on brokers and sellers. Thus the need

to integrate temporal analysis into case-based legal reasoning models arises in

many legal domains that affect large numbers of people, and presents a significant

challenge for those wishing to make case-based legal reasoning systems more

robust.

5. Procedural context: Modeling the process of legal decision-makin

In this section, we demonstrate that a robust model of legal cases must include a

representation of the procedural context of legal precedents. By procedural context,

we mean how a legal systems decision-making machinery was invoked to decide

a case. This includes the jurisdiction in which a legal action was heard; the level

and type of court that adjudicated it; and the formal process(es) of decision making

employed (which we call the procedural posture of the case). Such meta-level

legal concepts (that is, concepts that address the process of decision making rather

than its substance) permeate appellate court decisions and profoundly influence the

analysis and use of precedents.

Below, we show the importance of procedural posture in accurately modeling

case-based legal reasoning, focusing on the large subset of appellate cases decided

on the basis of either the sufficiency of pleadings or the sufficiency of the evidence.

Using examples from Massachusetts property law, we show that evaluating

a precedent based on factual similarity without considering its procedural posture

can result in unpersuasive or even erroneous legal arguments. We develop a formal

model of procedural posture that generates 10 procedurally-distinct types of legal

results, five favoring the plaintiff and five favoring the defendant. We then propose

rules describing, for each result type, which other result types function best as

precedents, and outline a method for incorporating these procedural distinctions

into case-based reasoning systems.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 49

5.1. A HYPOTHETICAL EXAMPLE

Consider the following hypothetical case used in a Property Law class:

In 1978 Ida Peat conveyed to Max Schnell an unimproved wooded area of

approximately five acres located in Boxtown, Massachusetts. Max was a

world renowned speed skater and traveled frequently abroad to compete and

train. In Spring 1979, Max had posted land marks at each corner of the lot,

and he paid taxes on the lot between 1978 and 1985. During the cold months

of 19781985 Max cleared a large area of the lot by removing trees and

bushes, and he flooded the cleared area for a practice rink. In June 1985, Max

conveyed the lot over to Sheila Spark and moved away. In July 1985, Sheila

moved onto the lot, put up fences along the borders and built a barn so she

could raise sheep. Since 1985 Sheila has continuously housed eight to twenty

sheep on the lot.

In December 1999, John Doe, who possesses document showing a valid

chain of title, has threatened to commence an action to establish his title to

the five-acre tract. No doubt exists that John has the superior record title.

You represent Sheila. John has offered to sell his interest in the land for

$50,000. Sheila values the land at $120,000 and you have estimated the costs

of litigation to be $20,000. Evaluate the merits of Johns settlement offer.

The students were aware of the doctrine of adverse possession, which permits an

occupant without formal title to land to obtain title to that land when there is:

(1) an actual entry giving exclusive possession that is (2) open and notorious, (3)

adverse and under a claim of right, and (4) continuous for the statutory period

of 20 years (Dukeminier 1988, p. 100). Most students recognize two questions of

continuity: first, can Sheila combine her 14 years with Maxs 7 years in order to get

the required 20 years of continuous possession? Second, did Maxs frequent trips

abroad and his failure to use the land throughout the year interrupt the continuity

of possession? From approximately 100 prior Massachusetts adverse possession

cases available to the students, we present below two cases in a frame-like summary

format often used by law students (Wren, p. 161), which resembles the frame-based

knowledge representations used by AI and Law researchers (Ashley 1990, p. 220;

Hafner 1987, p. 38).

The law students dutifully mapped each of the facts and legal issues of Sheilas

case to Kershaw. They reasoned that speed skating resembled circus performing;

land marks resembled pipes; both claimants by adverse possession cleared the land;

both adverse possessors paid the taxes; both had continuity problems since they

left the country; both cases involved combining the interest of a second adverse

possessor (who more fully developed the land) with that of a prior possessor.

Therefore, they concluded, Sheila should reject Johns settlement offer.

50 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Name: Kershaw v. Zecchini (Kershaw)

Citation: 342 Mass. 318, 173 N.E.2d 624

Date: 1961 Vote: 5-0 Judge: Spalding

Procedural Setting: Bill in equity by holder of record title is brought in the Land Court to obtain

a declaratory decree establishing title to a parcel of real estate. From a decree adjudging that the

defendant was the owner of the parcel by adverse possession, the plaintiffs appealed.

Facts: Plaintiffs had superior record title to a 5,000 square foot lot. The defendant claimed title

under a deed from Andresen and his wife. The Andresens were circus performers who travelled

extensively abroad. After his purchase represented by a deed, Andresen and the defendant went

onto the property, which had previously been unimproved land, and cleared the brush and put down

pipes at the corners of the lot and kept it clear. The land was assessed to him for taxes from 1937 to

1942. From 1936 until 1943 Andresen and the defendant exercised and practiced stunts on the lot

when they were in town. In consideration for payment of several years of back taxes on the land,

Andresen conveyed the property to the defendant in 1943. Thereafter the defendant erected a wall

and built the house which is now on the land.

Issues: Did the Land Court err in finding that the defendants obtained title to the parcel by adverse

possession.

Result: Decision of Land Court in favor of defendant is affirmed.

Reasoning: The Land Court was justified in deciding that as a matter of fact the actions of the

defendant were sufficient to constitute adverse possession. The defendant had marked the property;

the visits away from the property did not, as a matter of law, disrupt the continuity of possession.

Name: Senn v. Western Mass. Electric Co. (Senn)

Citation: 18 Mass.App. 992, 471 N.E.2d 131

Date: 1984 Vote: 3 Judge: Rescript

Procedural Setting: Defendant took an easement on a 56 acre parcel by eminent domain. The

plaintiffs who claimed ownership of the parcel by adverse possession sought damages. The

plaintiffs appeal the trial judges setting aside a jury verdict which awarded damages.

Facts: The plaintiffs and their predecessors had used, in some fashion, part of the parcel for at

least 20 years. The main activity during that time involved the cutting of timber for family use and

for sale to others. They used the logging roads traversing the parcel, pastured some animals over

a portion of the parcel, and paid real estate taxes in the years 1967 through 1970. The plaintiffs

conceded that they never enclosed the parcel by walls or fencing.

Issue: Did the trial judge correctly rule that as a matter of law the plaintiffs had failed to establish

ownership of the parcel by adverse possession?

Result: The decision of the trial judge setting aside the verdict for the plaintiffs is affirmed.

Reasoning: To establish adverse possession of open woodlands, as a matter of law the claimant

must show cultivation or enclosure.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 51

But, as the language in Kershaw makes clear, such a conclusion was unwarranted

because the appellate court merely affirmed a lower courts factual determination:

Whether, in a particular case, these elements [are sufficient to acquire title by

adverse possession] is essentially a question of fact. This is because . . . [t]he

nature and the extent of occupancy required to establish a right by adverse

possession vary with the character of the land, the purposes for which it is

adapted, and the uses to which it has been put. (173 N.E.2d 624, 626)

As explained in more detail below, although the appellate court in Kershaw upheld

the trial courts finding in favor of the adverse possessor, the same court could

(without contradicting itself) uphold a trial courts finding to the contrary. The

courts decision does not say that Kershaw was decided correctly, only that there

are not sufficient legal grounds for overturning it. Thus, from Kershaw one can only

infer that if (1) a trial court were to find for Sheila and (2) Sheilas case is similar

to Kershaw then (3) that finding would not be overturned. It says little about how a

trier of fact would decide Sheilas case.

A more sophisticated mapping strategy would have led students to perceive the

potential relevance of Senn, a subsequent case that purported to follow Kershaw.

In affirming the trial courts ruling that, as a matter of law, there was insufficient

evidence of adverse possession to go to the jury, the court in Senn held that:

[a]ccording to the cases decided inMassachusetts . . . these acts are not in their

nature acts of exclusive possession, and therefore do not constitute proof of

disseisin . . .Kershaw v. Zecchini is not to the contrary. (471 N.E.2d 131, 132)

But why isnt Kershaw to the contrary, since both parcels were undeveloped and

neither was enclosed or cultivated? Perhaps the distinction, although unstated, lies

in the relative sizes of the tracts. The parcel of land in Kershaw was about 5,000

square feet, roughly 1/8 of an acre, whereas the parcel in Senn was over 56 acres.

On a 1/8 acre parcel, almost any significant use could be reasonably viewed as

exclusive, open and notorious possession, while on a 56 acre tract the same

activity may have no obvious impact. Therefore, one should not, based on the

material presented in these two cases, conclude that a Massachusetts court would

treat Maxs five acre open tract of land like the 1/8 acre in Kershaw rather than like

the 56 acres in Senn.

Most experienced litigators would engage in a process of decision analysis in

applying these two cases to these specific facts. First, the litigator must decide

whether Sheila, as a matter of law, will be barred from gaining title by adverse possession

byMaxs failure to take those acts required for adverse possession of a tract

of open woodlands. To answer that question the lawyer must decide whether a

judge will, as a matter of law, characterize this five acre tract as open woodlands.

If the land is so characterized then the lawyer must decide whether the judge, as

a matter of law, will rule that Maxs actions failed to constitute cultivation or

enclosure. Before predicting how a court would decide these questions of law,

most experienced practitioners would obtain additional facts about the size of the

52 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

area that Max cleared for use as a skating rink, and the visibility of the markers and

Maxs activities to an owner who casually surveyed his property. In the absence

of facts showing that Max used most of the five acre tract and that the markers

and Maxs activities were highly visible, many practitioners would, given Senn,

recommend accepting Johns offer.

If the lawyer decides that Sheilas claim is not barred as a matter of law, then

her lawyer must further assess the chances of persuading a trier of fact to find in

her favor. This assessment would be based on the attorneys sense of what a given

judge or jury thinks is the just result in the given case. Since Sheila believed she

had good title, used the property for many years, paid the taxes and made a heavy

investment in the property, most litigators would probably conclude that the factual

issue would be resolved in Sheilas favor.

5.2. A COMPUTATIONAL MODEL OF PROCEDURAL CONTEXT

In most common law jurisdictions, legal issues are characterized three ways. First,

a judge or jury may decide an issue as a question of fact. If Sheila claims that

Max practiced every day and John claims that Max practiced only occasionally,

the question of how often Max practiced is a question for the trier of fact to decide.

If a trial court, after hearing all the testimony, decides as a finding of fact that

Max practiced every day, this finding can only be overturned on appeal if it is

clearly erroneous, a most difficult standard to satisfy.

Second, an issue may be resolved as a question of law. In these situations, even

if one assumes all disputed facts are decided in a manner favorable to one party, that

party still cannot win. The disposition of cases as matters of law fall into several

categories. In some situations (e.g., judgment on the pleadings) the rule is clear and

the lawyer can do nothing to change the result by building a richer fact record. If

Massachusetts had a rule that no one can obtain title to registered land by adverse

possession, then Sheila loses if the disputed parcel was registered.

In other situations (e.g., summary judgment), cases are resolved as a matter

of law because a partys evidence, even if believed, is not sufficient to satisfy

the requirements of their claim a decision that may involve open-textured legal

concepts. The court in Senn, following earlier precedents, held as a matter of law

that title by adverse possession of open woodlands requires either enclosure or

cultivation. After reading Senn, Sheilas attorney would undoubtedly try to find

witnesses or photographs showing that Max used a portion of the land for a garden,

or built a fence around his practice rink. Or the lawyer might try to argue that a

5-acre lot does not qualify as open woodland within the meaning of Senn.

Third, there are mixed issues of fact and law. These are cases where legal rules

are applied to the facts to determine who wins the case. In Sheilas case the trier

of fact, be it judge or jury, must decide whether Maxs actions of cutting bushes,

placing markers, paying taxes, etc., amounted to adverse possession. Significant

indeterminacy arises in the process of characterizing mixed questions of law and

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 53

fact and deciding who should decide these questions. In Kershaw the court was

comfortable leaving the decision to the trier of fact while in Senn the court, in

order to protect the interest of owners of large tracts of open woodlands, had the

case turn on a question of law.

To allow certain issues to be decided as questions of law, legislatures and courts

have crafted formal procedures. These procedures are described below, along with

a formal representation consisting of:

a. a three-stage model of legal decision making,

b. a classification of legal decisions into 10 procedure-based result types (5

favoring each side), and

c. rules that describe the procedural relevance of a prior case to a current case,

depending on the procedural categories of the two cases.

5.2.1. A three-stage model of legal decision making

We begin by classifying the results of litigation into the pleading stage (PL), the

pre-verdict stage (PV) and the trial verdict stage (TV). Both the PL and PV stages

represent the disposition of a case as a matter of law, while the TV stage represents

the disposition of a case as a matter of fact, or a mixed question of law and fact

which is decided by the trier of fact.

In the pleading stage (PL), cases can be dismissed after the plaintiffs complaint

on the grounds that the complaint fails to state a cause of action. If John failed to

allege that he had a valid title to the parcel, then Sheila could seek immediate

dismissal on this ground. Second, cases can be decided on the pleadings. If Sheila

in her answer alleges facts that amount to only 18 years of possession, then John

could seek a judgment based on the pleadings. The PL stage is concerned with the

rules that set forth the required elements of legal claims and defenses; and verifying

that each side alleges a minimal set of facts that satisfy the requirements of these

rules.Modeling this stage is more an exercise in rule-based reasoning because these

requirements are set forth in statutes or rules that may be inferred from the holdings

of decided cases.

In the pre-verdict stage (PV), after completing the process of discovery and

examining depositions, interrogatories, plot plans, photographs, etc., a court might

grant Johns motion for summary judgment on the grounds that as a matter of law

the parcel was open woodland and Max failed to enclose or cultivate the land. Or,

after the presentation of all the evidence at a trial, a judge might direct a verdict

in Johns favor on the same grounds. Or, the trial judge might allow the case to go

to a jury, and after a jury finding in favor of Sheila might grant Johns motion for

judgment notwithstanding the jury verdict on the same grounds. Judges use judgments

notwithstanding the verdict for reasons of judicial economy. Often, one side

may have a very weak case and the judge believes a jury will find for the stronger

side on issues of fact, thereby making an appeal very difficult to win. Second, if

the trial judges directed verdict is overturned on appeal, then the case must be

re-tried; if the trial judge instead grants a judgment notwithstanding the verdict

54 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

then on appeal the jurys verdict can be re-instated. Although subtle differences

exist among summary judgment, directed verdict, and judgment notwithstanding

the verdict, these three methods of disposing of cases can be treated the same for

purposes of our analysis, since in all three situations the court rules as a matter of

law that the evidence offered is insufficient to create an issue for a trier of fact to

decide. The trial verdict stage (TV) involves a decision by the trier of fact, be it a

judge or jury. If the two sides present witnesses who give conflicting testimony, the

trier of fact must decide which testimony is most convincing. The trier of fact must

also decide such mixed questions of fact and law as whether the activities of Max

from 1969-1975 amounted to adverse possession.

5.2.2. Classification of legal results

The formal decision-making procedures described above define a complex array

of legal questions that come before appellate courts, and the significance of an

appellate decision can only be understood in its procedural context. Synopses found

in case reporters and digests typically begin with the procedural context of the case,

as illustrated by the case descriptions presented in Section 5.1. The rows of Table

III represent legal decisions under a variety of procedural scenarios; although they

constitute only a subset of the actual scenarios that confront the expert attorney,

they are sufficient to demonstrate how procedural context influences legal casebased

reasoning.

Following the three-stage model of legal decision making, we can (assuming

the equivalences of certain dispositions) represent legal results using three basic

predicates:22

1. PL(Side1, C) Side 1 of case C is entitled to judgment at the pleading stage.

2. PV(Side1, C) Side 1 of case C is entitled to judgment at the pre-verdict stage.

3. TV(Side1, C) A trial verdict in favor of Side1 in case C should be upheld.

Assuming Side1 and Side2 represent opposing parties, and the result of a case

must be a positive or negative instance of one of the three basic predicates, there are

12 legal propositions to choose from in characterizing the result of a case. However,

the equivalence:

TV(Side1, C).PV(Side2, C)

(i.e., reversal of a trial verdict in favor of Side 1 is legally equivalent to a directed

verdict for Side 2) reduces this to only 10 distinct legal results. Table 3 enumerates

the 32 common legal scenarios that arise from our 3-stage model of legal decision

making; the rightmost column shows the legal result type associated with each

scenario. (Due to the equivalence shown above, there are no negative instances of

the TV predicate.)

Let us consider how the cases described in Section 5.1 would be categorized.

Since the party claiming by adverse possession may be either the plaintiff or defendant,

we will use AP and RT to represent the two sides instead of the traditional

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 55

P and D. In Senn, the plaintiff (AP) won a trial verdict, but the trial judge granted

RTs motion to set aside the verdict, and this was affirmed on appeal. This case

corresponds to scenario 4 in Table III ( equivalent to a directed verdict for the

defendant), so the legal result is: PV(RT, Senn). In Kershaw, the defendant (AP)

won a trial verdict and it was upheld, which corresponds to scenario 1 and legal

result TV(AP, Kershaw).

5.2.3. Procedure-based rules of relevance

To complete our analysis of procedural context in case-based legal reasoning, we

consider how the precedential value of a prior case depends on the result type of the

prior case and the result type we want to obtain in the current case. For example,

Kershaw is a highly relevant precedent in arguing against a directed verdict in favor

of John, since it holds that adverse possession is a question of fact. However, if a

jury trial occurred and John won, Kershaw would not be a highly relevant precedent

in arguing that the verdict should be set aside. So, it is not sufficient to classify

Kershaw as a result that favors the adverse possessor, as would be done in most

legal case-based reasoning models. In some procedural contexts, such as an appeal

by Sheila of a jury verdict favoring John, Kershaw with its strong statement about

adverse possession being a question of fact could by cited by John in arguing that

the verdict favoring him should be upheld!

Of course, procedural relevance alone cannot make a strong precedent; it is also

important that the cases have similar fact situations. In the discussion that follows,

we assume that the prior case is factually similar to the current case, and consider

only the effect of procedural context on the strength of the precedent. In Section

5.3, we consider how procedural and factual relevance judgments can be combined

in a single algorithm for determining the most relevant prior case.

Table IV shows procedure-based rules of relevance. Assuming factual similarity,

the procedural relevance of a prior case to a new case will be classified as

strong, weak, or not relevant. An example of a strongly supportive precedent would

be the use of Kershaw by Sheila in a scenario where John appeals a trial verdict

in Sheilas favor. An example of a weakly supportive precedent would be the use

of Kershaw by John in a scenario where Sheila appeals a trial verdict in Johns

favor. We claim that a case which upholds a trial verdict in favor of one side may

(depending on the language of the decision) have precedential value for upholding

a trial verdict in favor of either side.

5.2.4. Integrating procedural context into case-based legal reasoning

To date, models of case-based legal reasoning have concentrated on representing

and matching the substantive facts and issues, and have not taken account of procedural

variations. As described in Section 2, in the HYPO system (Ashley 1990;

Rissland and Ashley 1987), cases are described and indexed by legally relevant

56 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

Table III. A catalog of procedural scenarios

Procedural scenario Precedent type

1. Side2 wins jury verdict Side1 appeals Verdict upheld TV(Side2, c)

2. Verdict reversed PV(Side1, c)

3. Side1 wins jury verdict Side2 appeals Verdict upheld TV(Side1, c)

4. Verdict reversed PV(Side2, c)

5. Judgment NOV for Side2 Side1 appeals judgment upheld PV(Side2, c)

6. Judgment reversed TV(Side1, c)

7. Judgment NOV for Side1 Side2 appeals judgment upheld PV(Side1, c)

8. Judgment reversed TV(Side2, c)

9. Side1 moves for Directed Verdict Granted Affirmed PV(Side1, c)

(after trial)

10. Reversed. PV(Side1, c)

11. (equivalent to scenario 1) Not granted Affirmed TV(Side2, c)

12. (equivalent to scenario 2) Reversed PV(Side1, c)

13. Side2 moves for Directed Verdict Granted Affirmed PV(Side2, c)

(after trial)

14. Reversed. PV(Side2, c)

15. (equivalent to scenario 3) Not granted Affirmed TV(Side1, c)

16. (equivalent to scenario 4) Reversed PV(Side2, c)

17. Side1 moves for summary judgment Granted Affirmed PV(Side1, c)

(before trial)

18. Reversed. PV(Side1, c)

19. Not granted Affirmed. PV(Side1, c)

20. Reversed PV(Side1, c)

21. Side2 moves for summary judgment Granted Affirmed PV(Side2, c)

(before trial)

22. Reversed. PV(Side2, c)

23. Not granted Affirmed. PV(Side2, c)

24. Reversed PV(Side2, c)

25. Side1 moves for judgment on pleadings Granted Affirmed PL(Side1, c)

26. Reversed. PL(Side1, c)

27. Not granted Affirmed. PL(Side1, c)

28. Reversed PL(Side1, c)

29. Side2 moves for judgment on pleadings Granted Affirmed PL(Side2, c)

30. Reversed. PL(Side2, c)

31. Not granted Affirmed. PL(Side2, c)

32. Reversed PL(Side2, c)

.Remanded for additional lower-court proceedings.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 57

Table IV. Procedure-based rules of relevance

Prior results Desired result Procedural relevance

PL(Side1, PC) PL(Side1, CC) Strong

PV(Side1, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Strong

TV(Side1, PC) TV(Side1, CC) Strong

PL(Side1, PC) PL(Side1, CC) Strong

PV(Side1, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Strong

A prior holding of a basic result is a strong precedent for the

same result in a later case.

PV(Side2, PC) TV(Side1, CC) Strong

TV(Side2, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Strong

A prior holding that Side2 is not entitled to a directed

verdict is a strong precedent for upholding a trial verdict

for Side1 and vice versa.

PV(Side2, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Strong

PL(Side2, PC) PL(Side1, CC) Strong

A prior holding that Side2 should win as a matter of law is a

strong precedent against Side1 achieving the same result.

PL(Side1, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Strong

PV(Side1, PC) TV(Side1, CC) Strong

PV(Side1, PC) PL(Side1, CC) Strong

PV(Side2, PC) PL(Side1, CC) Strong

TV(Side2, PC) PL(Side1, CC) Strong

A stronger prior result is a precedent for a weaker result

favoring the same side. For example, a case that rules Side1

is entitled to summary judgement can be used to argue it is

entitled a fortiori to have a verdict in its favor affirmed.

PV(Side2, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Weak

TV(Side2, PC) TV(Side1, CC) Weak

TV(Side1, PC) PV(Side1, CC) Weak

PV(Side1, PC) TV(Side1, CC) Weak

A prior holding that Side2 is not entitled summary judgment, and

that moves the case forward to trial, may be useful to argue that

Side1 is also not entitled to summary judgment, especially if it

says certain issues must be decided by the trier of fact. The same

argument applies when a trial verdict is upheld. However these

precedents are not as strong as a prior case whose holding favors

the same side as the current case.

58 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

factors or dimensions, which are used to search for relevant precedents, and to

construct legal arguments.

Above we have described the complexity of actual reported cases, in which

holdings on fact-based issues are intermingled with procedural rulings, and we

have argued that there are at least 10 distinct types of results or holdings that need

to be represented in a case-based legal reasoning system. Assuming the existence

of a system along the lines of HYPO for creating a similarity ranking of cases using

factors, it is reasonable to ask how our model of procedural context could be used

to improve it.

One simple approach would be to continue to build the similarity ranking,

without regard to procedural context, select the factually on point cases, and

then use the legal result type as a filter to select those that are procedurally relevant

as well. However, from the standpoint of efficiency, in a practical system with large

numbers of precedents, ranking the precedents based on factual similarity requires

a great deal of computation. In circumstances where many of those cases may not

be procedurally relevant, it would be more efficient to apply the filter first, and then

rank those cases known to be procedurally relevant.

Following is an outline of an algorithm for selecting procedurally relevant

precedents to be included in a fact-based similarity ranking.

1. Assign one party to Side1, and determine the result type(s) to be advocated by

that party.

2. Select rows from Table IV, where the value of the center column, Desired

Result, is one of the result types from Step1.

3. Make a list of the values in the leftmost column of the selected rows, and mark

them to indicate whether they provide strong or weak support.

4. Select cases from the database whose result type is a member of the list created

in Step 3, and mark them according to whether they provide strong or weak

support for Side1.

Steps 58. Repeat Steps 14, but use the negations of the result types from Step 1.

The selected cases comprise the input to the fact-based matching process that results

in a relevance ranking of prior cases. For example, if Sheilas attorney wants

to find precedents that support a motion to dismiss Johns claim at the pleading

stage, the basic result corresponding to this motion (assigning Side1 to Sheila) is

PL(Side1, CC) and the opposing result is PL(Side1, CC). In Step 2, the following

row would be retrieved:

PL(Side1, PC) PL(Side1, CC) strong

In Step 6, the following rows would be retrieved:

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 59

PL(Side2, PC) PL(Side1, CC) strong

PV(Side1, PC) PL(Side1, CC) strong

PV(Side2, PC) PL(Side1, CC) strong

TV(Side2, PC) PL(Side1, CC) strong

The results of filtering would restrict substantive analysis to six of the 10 result

types, since the other four result types would not be relevant precedents for this

motion. For example, the fact that a trial verdict was directed in favor of an adverse

possessor in a prior case (PV(Side1, PC)) does not imply that in a similar case

Sheila should (or should not) prevail at the pleading stage, since a judgment at the

pleading stage is a stronger result than a directed verdict. However, a case where

the court refused a motion for a directed verdict in favor of the adverse possessor

(PV(Side1, PC)) implies that in a similar case Sheila should not prevail at the

pleading stage, so Johns attorney could cite such as case in arguing against Sheilas

motion.

Some procedure-driven differences would also occur in the process of arguing

with cases once their factual similarity with a current case has been evaluated.

In existing legal case-based reasoning systems, the result or holding of a case is

represented as a binary choice: case favors plaintiff or case favors defendant. This

may lead to the incorrect use of precedents in some procedural contexts; for example,

a case such as Kershaw, whose result favored the adverse possessor, would

be useless to the adverse possessor (and weakly supportive to the other side) in

arguing a motion by the adverse possessor for a summary judgment.

Finally, there is a need to consider the implications of using a strong v. weak

classification of procedural relevance, and its interaction with ranking of precedents

by factual similarity. If two prior cases are equally on point (which often occurs

with a partial ordering framework such as HYPO uses), then if only one has strong

procedural relevance, that case is clearly a better precedent. However, further empirical

study is needed to analyze how a case should viewed which is more on point

factually but only weakly relevant procedurally.

5.3. IMPLICATIONS FOR LEGAL ARGUMENTATION SYSTEMS

Lawyers spend many waking hours reasoning from cases, with the goal of developing

persuasive legal arguments. To contribute to the basic education of lawyers, or

to realize Ashleys dream of mak[ing] a prototype for a Brief Writers Assistant

(Ashley 1988, p. 216) computational models of cases must accurately represent

the procedural posture of the case. For example, a system based on the three-stage

model proposed above could, replicating a HYPO-style argument, generate the

following procedurally-correct argument for Sheila:

POINT for adverse possessor (AP) in appealing a directed verdict granted

to the record title holder (RT):

60 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

WHERE: AP and APs predecessor entered under color of title, used the land

continually for a 20 year period, paid taxes on the land, and placed markers at

the boundaries of the land, AP should not be barred by law from a claim of

adverse possession.

CITE: In Kershaw, the court held that whether entering undeveloped land,

paying taxes, and placing markers at the boundary could amount to adverse

possession was a question of fact.

RESPONSE for RT:

Kershaw is distinguishable because in Kershaw the tract of land was 1/8 of an

acre. Max entered onto a 5 acre parcel.

CITE: Senn holds that as a matter of law, to gain title of open woodlands by

adverse possession the claimant must cultivate or enclose the land and AP did

not cultivate or enclose this parcel.

REBUTTAL for AP:

Senn is distinguishable because in Senn the tract of land was 56 acres. Max

entered a 5 acre tract, which is not, as a matter of law, open woodlands within

the meaning of Senn.

Although the robustness of case-based legal reasoning is enhanced by the model

of procedural context proposed above, there are still many issues that must be

addressed to create an adequate model of the procedural posture of cases. The

parties to a dispute dont always fall into the standard opposing categories: for

example, some cases involve two adverse possessors, neither of whom can claim

record title ownership. The relief being sought must also be considered: often

plaintiffs seek a mix of declaratory relief, damages, and a specific relief such as

injunctions, ejectment or mandamus. The most serious impediment to an accurate

computational model of procedural context is the lack of a binary set of trial court

and appellate court dispositions. Appellate courts can choose from an array of

dispositions by affirming, reversing, remanding, affirming in part and remanding

in part, reversing in part and affirming in part, or remanding in part and reversing

in part. And appellate courts can reverse or affirm on grounds that have nothing to

do with the sufficiency of the pleadings or the evidence: for example on the grounds

that inadequate instructions were given to the jury.

A truly robust system for case-based legal reasoning must be able to precisely

represent these complex variations, and draw the correct inferences from them

when considering the likelihood that a prior case will be judged relevant by a later

court, and if it is judged relevant, how it will influence the courts rulings.

6. Conclusions

We have argued that the contextual aspects of legal decisions - procedural, teleological

and temporal are important components of case-based legal reasoning,

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 61

and we have begun here to explore ways of incorporating context into case-based

reasoning systems. We have shown how these extended computational models can

be used to make legal analysis more accurate and legal arguments more realistic.

Though incomplete, our proposed context-informed arguments more closely

approximate real world advocacy in common law jurisdictions. Granted, there is

a limit to the levels of abstraction that one could incorporate into a case-based

reasoner, so we cannot replicate the full range of argument moves found in the

arsenal of a truly gifted advocate. Nonetheless, we anticipate that case-based

reasoners incorporating contextual knowledge will prove useful to less experienced

attorneys, and to legal educators who want to enhance the advocacy skills of their

students (Aleven and Ashley 1994).

The formal representations and algorithms proposed in this paper have the potential

to enhance the robustness of legal case-based reasoning systems; however

they are only a start. There is much basic research remaining to be done, to understand

fully the contextual influences on the use of legal precedents and their

potential for computational realization. The analyses of procedural, teleological,

and temporal dimensions of context need to be elaborated and tested using other

legal domains. The influence of other contextual dimensions also needs to be considered,

for example, the influence of legal jurisdiction is increasingly significant

in the global economy. The social and economic characteristics of the parties to

a legal dispute is another aspect of context that cannot be ignored when trying to

understand the significance of legal precedents.

The analysis presented in this paper raises many more questions than it answers

questions that ought to be the subject of continuing research by the artificial

intelligence and law community.

Notes

1 The material in this paper has been edited and expanded by the first author after the untimely death

of Donald Berman in 1997 (see the Editors Introduction and other articles in this memorial volume

for tributes to Don and discussions of his many contributions). The three conference papers are

presented in Sections 35 below, with no substantive additions, but with some modifications for the

sake of clarity, brevity, and editorial unity. This Introduction (Section 1), Section 2, and Section 6 are

new. For each of the three conference-paper-based Sections, a revised Introduction puts the material

to follow into context and a few selected additional (and later) references are included besides those

that appeared in the original version. There is no attempt, however, to provide a general review of the

state of the art in case-based reasoning legal reasoning since 1995. The 1993 paper, which generated

the most comment and interest from the AI and Law community, is presented first in Section 3.

That paper has been shortened by removing a second set of example cases, which analyzed the

open-textured concept of an event occurring in the course of employment from U.S. workers

compensation law.

2 Some more recent legal CBR systems, notably BANKXX (Rissland et al. 1996) include other

forms of remembered experience (such as argument moves) in addition to judicial opinions in their

knowledge bases.

3 The algorithm for computing similarity need not be numerical; in HYPO, for instance, it is based

on inclusiveness of sets of shared dimensions, as described below.

62 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

4 HYPO evolved over the time period of its development (approximately 19841990); the description

below and other references to the HYPO model in this paper are based on the doctoral thesis

of Kevin Ashley (1990). A historical analysis of HYPOs development and its influence on future

systems appears in Rissland and Ashley (2002) in this volume. That article also points out some

differences between HYPOs model of dimensions and the approach used in Sections 3 through 5 of

this paper.

5 The classification of factors or dimensions as favoring one side of a legal dispute was not part of

earlier (pre-1990) versions of HYPO (see Rissland and Ashley 2002 in this volume). In this paper,

when we say a factor favors a side, we mean that a value of true (for a binary factor) or a larger value

(for a quantitative factor) favors that side.

6 See Ashley (1990, pp. 147154.)

7 3 Cai. R. 175, 2 Am Dec 264 (Supreme Court of New York 1805).

8 11 East 574, 103 Eng. Rep 1127 (Queens Bench 1707).

9 1 Dav. and Mer. 592, 6 Q.B. 606 (1844).

10 We have inferred from the reported opinions the policy arguments that were considered in Young

because cases were argued orally, and written briefs are not available. Also, since opinions were

delivered orally and transcribed by reporters, the opinions tended to be rather short. Finally, common

law judges used a form of verbal shorthand that embodied their policy determinations. As evidence

that these kinds of arguments are routinely considered in law school classes, see Dukeminier and

Krier (1988, pp. 820).

11 This is an example of how the procedural context of a legal dispute can determine the result, as

discussed in Section 5 below.

12 Ontario Re. Stat. (1960), ch. 172, Sec. 105.

13 12 N.Y.2d 473, 191 N.E.2d 279, 473 N.Y.S.2d 279 (1963).

14 277 N.Y. 407, 14 N.E.2d 455 (1938).

15 294 N.Y. 288, 62 N.E. 2d 74 (1945).

16 Ward et al. v. Strobel, 300 N.Y. 294, 90 N.E.2d 467 (1949), Fortuna v. Sangster, 59 N.Y. S. 2d 190

(1945), Harry Turnowski v. Aaron Turnowski, 33 Misc 2d 864, 226 N.Y.S.2d 738 (1962).

17 5 N.Y.2d 1016.

18 308 N.Y. 155, 124 N.E.2d 99 (1954).

19 9 N.Y.2d 554, 175 N.E.2d 441, 216 N.Y.S.2d 65 (1961).

20 9 N.Y.2d 34, 172 N.E.2d 526, 211 N.Y.S.2d 133 (1961).

21 24 N.Y.2d 569, 301 N.Y.S.2d 519, 249 N.E. 2d 394 (1969).

22 In applying this model to a particular legal domain, Side1 and Side2 can be replaced by more

specific descriptions such as Plaintiff and Defendant (P and D), or Adverse-Possessor and Record-

Title-Holder (AP and RT).

References

Ashley, K. D. (1990).Modeling Legal Argument: Reasoning with Cases and Hypotheticals. Bradford

Books/MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.

Ashley, K. D. (1988). Arguing by Analogy in Law: A Case-Based Model. In Helman, D. (ed.),

Analogical Reasoning, 205224. Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands.

Ashley, K. D. and Rissland, E. L. (1987). But, See, Accord: Generating Blue Book Citations in

HYPO. In Proceedings of the First International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law,

6774. ACM Press: New York.

Aleven, V. and Ashley, K. D. (1994). An Instructional Environment for Practicing Argumentation

Skills. In Proceedings of the 10th National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI-94),

485492. AAAI Press: Menlo Park, CA.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN CASE-BASED LEGAL REASONING 63

Berman, D. H. and Hafner, C. D. (1991). Incorporating Procedural Context into a Model of

Case-Based Legal Reasoning. In Proceedings of the 3rd International Conference on Artificial

Intelligence and Law, 1220. ACM Press: New York.

Berman, D. H. and Hafner, C. D. (1993). Representing Teleological Structure in Case-Based Legal

Reasoning: The Missing Link. In Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Artificial

Intelligence and Law, 5060. ACM Press: New York.

Berman, D. H. and Hafner, C. D. (1995). Understanding Precedents in a Temporal Context of

Evolving Legal Doctrine. In Proceedings of the 5th International Conference on Artificial

Intelligence and Law, 4251. ACM Press: New York.

Berman, D. H. (1989). The Need for a Medium Grain Choice of Law Filter in Certain Legal Expert

Systems. In Martino, A. (ed.) Pre-Proceedings of the Third International Conference on Logica

Informatica Diritto, 6581. Consiglio Nazionale delle Richerche: Florence.

Branting, K. (1991). Reasoning with Portions of Precedents. In Proceedings of the 3rd International

Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 145154. ACM Press: New York.

Branting, K. (1994). A Computational Model of Ratio Decidendi. Artificial Intelligence and Law

2(1): 131.

Cuthill, B. and McCartney, R. (1994). Issue Spotting in CHASER. Artificial Intelligence and Law

2(2): 83111.

Dukeminier, J. and Krier, J. (1988). Teachers Manual, Property Law, 2nd ed. Little, Brown: Boston,

MA.

Frank, J. (1930). Law and the Modern Mind. Brentanos: New York.

Fuller, L. (1958). Positivism and Fidelity to Law A Reply to Professor Hart. 71 Harvard Law

Review 630

Gardner, A. (1987). An Artificial Intelligence Approach to Legal Reasoning. Bradford Books/MIT

Press: Cambridge, MA.

Gordon, T. F. (1994). The Pleadings Game: An Exercise in Computational Dialectics. Artificial

Intelligence and Law 2(4): 239292.

Groendijk, C. and Oskamp, A. (1993). Case Recognition and Strategy Classification. In Proceedings

of the 4th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 125132. ACM Press:

New York.

Hafner, C. D. (1981). An Information Retrieval System Based on a Computer Model of Legal

Knowledge. Ph.D. Thesis, The University of Michigan. UMI Research Press: Ann Arbor, MI.

Hafner, C. D. (1987). Conceptual Organization of Case Law Knowledge Bases. In Proceedings of

the First International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 3542. ACM Press: New

York.

Hart, H. L. A. (1958). Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. 71 Harvard Law Review

593.

Hayes-Roth, F.,Waterman, D. A., and Lenat. D. B. (eds.) (1983). Building Expert Systems. Addison-

Wesley: Reading, MA.

Hage, J. C., Leenes, R., and Lodder, A. N. (1994). Hard Cases: A Procedural Approach. Artificial

Intelligence and Law 2(2): 113167.

Hohfeld, W. N. (1913). Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning. 23 Yale

Law J. 16.

Holmes, O. (1897). The Path of the Law. Harvard Law Review 10: 457.

Kennedy, D. (1991). A Semiotics of Legal Argument. Syracuse Law Review 42(1): 75116.

Kuhn, T. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL.

Leake, D. B. (ed.) (1996). Case-Based Reasoning: Experiences, Lessons and Future Directions.

AAAI Press/MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.

Loui, R. P. and Norman, J. (1995). Rationales and Argument Moves. Artificial Intelligence and Law

3(3): 159185.

64 CAROLE D. HAFNER AND DONALD H. BERMAN

McCarty, L. T. and Sridharan, N. S. (1981). The Representation of an Evolving System of Legal

Concepts II: Prototypes and Deformations. Proceedings of IJCAI-81, 246253.

Prakken, H. and Sartor, G. (1997). A Dialectical Model of Assessing Conflicting Arguments in Legal

Reasoning. In Prakken, H. and Sartor, G. (eds.), Logical Models of Legal Argumentation, 175

212. Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands.

Riesbeck, C. K. and Schank, R. C. (1989). Inside Case-Based Reasoning. Lawrence Erlbaum:

Hillsdale, N.J.

Rissland, E. L. (1985). Argument Moves and Hypotheticals. In Walters, C. (ed.), Computing Power

and Legal Reasoning, 129143. West Publishing Co.: St. Paul, MN.

Rissland, E. L., Valcarce, E. M., and Ashley, K. D. (1984). Explaining and Arguing with Examples.

Proceedings of the Fourth National on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI-84), 288294, Austin, TX.

Rissland, E. L. and Ashley, K. D. (1987). A Case-Based System for Trade Secrets Law. In Proceedings

of the First International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 6167. ACM Press:

New York.

Rissland, E. L. and Skalak, D. B. (1991) CABARET: Statutory Interpretation in a Hybrid Architecture.

International Journal of Man-Machine Studies (34): 839887.

Rissland, E. L., Skalak, D. B., and Friedman, M. T. (1996). BankXX: Supporting Legal Arguments

through Heuristic Retrieval. Artificial Intelligence and Law 4(1): 171.

Rissland, E. L. and Ashley, K. D. (2002). A Note on Dimensions and Factors. Artificial Intelligence

and Law 10.

Rose, D. E. (1994). A Symbolic and Connectionist Approach to Legal Information Retrieval.

Lawrence Erlbaum: Hillsdale, NJ.

Schank, R. and Leake, D. (1990). Creativity and Learning in a Case-based Explainer. In Carbonnell,

J. (ed.), Machine Learning: Paradigms and Methods, 354385. MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.

Sanders, K. (1994). CHIRON: Planning in an Open-Textured Domain. Ph.D. diss., Technical Report

94-38, Computer Science Dept., Brown University, Providence RI.

Skalak, D. and Rissland, E. L. (1992) Arguments and Cases: An Inevitable Intertwining. Artificial

Intelligence and Law 1(1): 34.

Smith, J. C. and Deedman, C. (1987). The Application of Expert Systems Technology to Case-Based

Law. In Proceedings of the First International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law,

8493. ACM Press: New York.

Vossos, G., Zeleznikow, J., Dillon, T., and Vossos, V. (1991). An Example of Integrating Legal Case

Based Reasoning with Object Oriented Rule-Based Systems: IKBALS II. In Proceedings of the

3rd International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 3141. ACM Press: New York.

Wren, C. and Wren. J. (1986). The Legal Research Manual: A Game Plan for Legal Research and

Analysis. Abrams and Ambrose: Madison, WI.

 

Retirado de: http://www.kluweronline.com